Speranza
Mark Morford's survey of philosophy in the Roman world states its purpose
clearly at the outset.
The preface begins with a tribute to the two volumes on
Philosophia Togata edited by Griffin and Barnes (Oxford University Press,
1989 and 1997), and the conception of Roman philosophy as something essentially
Greek wrapped up in the dress of the Roman cultural elite dominates the book.
The first chapter takes the phrase as its title.
Morford, best known for his
work in Roman literature, declares his aims frankly.
"I am not a professional philosopher, and I have not attempted to
discuss matters of interest primarily to professional philosophers in any
detail. I have written as a classicist and historian of ideas, with the aim of
providing a concise, but not superficial survey of the writings and ideas of the
principal philosophers in the Roman world from the middle of the second century
BCE down to the death of Marcus Aurelius in 180 CE."
Classicists, like this reviewer, who regard the intellectual content of
ancient philosophical works as essential to any understanding of them,
might be disappointed by this aim.
There is a large and growing audience for
studies of Latin philosophical writing carried out as part of the history of
philosophy rather than the history of ideas.
But it is also true that there is a
great need for a book which outlines the development of philosophical writing in
Roman culture from an extra-philosophical standpoint.
A more up-to-date
historical survey than Gregor Maurach's useful Geschichte der römischen
Philosophie: eine Einführung (Darmstadt 1997), and one in English, would be
very welcome if well executed.
Despite some signal merits, though, Morford's
book does not fully satisfy this need.
The main body of the book is organized on chronological principles, though
there are many minor exceptions to allow for thematic connections (not all of
which seem warranted).
After a 14 page introductory chapter, Morford devotes
about 20 pages (chapter 2) to the important developments which brought Greek
philosophy to Rome in the second century BC, beginning with the famous embassy
of 155.
The LEGENDS about Pythagorean influence in Rome's earliest years and an
account of the history of Greek cultural influence on Rome are handled deftly in
the introduction.
CICERONE and his immediate intellectual context get almost 65 pages (chapter
3), though Lucretius is excluded from this discussion.
He and the Epicureans are
segregated in chapter 4, just over 30 pages -- a chapter which breaks more
seriously with the chronological plan of the book by considering Epicureanism
from the founder to Diogenes of Oenoanda.
This makes it very hard to gain a
clear picture of larger historical developments in various periods.
(The
Imperial period in which Diogenes worked is treated on its own in chapter 8,
solely from the point of view of Stoicism and Platonism.)
It is clear that
Morford regards Epicureanism as an unimportant phenomenon in philosophy, of
interest mostly for its reception in Latin literature.
Even so, it is
disappointing that he should have absorbed the ideological reaction of some
Romans to the school (marginalization) without seriously considering its deeper
role in Roman intellectual life outside of its impact on Horace and other
poets.
Morford's view of what counts in Roman philosophy is also reflected in the
fact that chapter 5, on philosophers and poets in the Augustan age, is nearly as
long as the entire treatment of Epicureanism.
The periodization here perhaps
makes some literary sense, but it is certainly less than ideal for the history
of ideas -- we may note how Varro, for example, winds up divided between the
Cicero chapter and the Augustan chapter in such a way that one cannot easily get
a clear picture of what this grand intellectual was all about.
The best parts of
this chapter are on Horace, Virgil, and the sub-philosophical Manilius.
The
chapter tells us a bit about Sextius and his followers, and provides an
out-of-date sketch of what we used to think we knew about Arius Didymus (a
philosopher at Augustus' court) along with a word or two about other familiar
figures.
But nowhere do we find a general account of philosophical developments
in the late Republic and Augustan period which depend on Rome's cultural and
political dominance.
Yet these issues should be part of Roman philosophy on
Morford's own announced principles.
Seneca and (some of) his contemporaries (chapter 6) are surveyed in even
fewer pages (27) than are devoted to the literary themes of the Augustan age.
The large theme of Stoicism in the Neronian and Flavian eras (chapter 7) gets
even less room (20 pages) and the book concludes with a chapter of 30 pages
(chapter 8) on Epictetus, Plutarch, Apuleius, Marcus Aurelius and some minor
contemporaries (including a paragraph for each of Galen and Sextus Empiricus).
Throughout the book one gets the sense that important opportunities have been
missed and confusion generated, even though there are many places where the
discussion is enlightening and the historical survey useful.
All too often the
reader's grasp of the subject will be disrupted by Morford's frequent failures
to understand adequately the subjects about which he writes and by the
inconsistent principles determining whom to include.
The clearest example of
this is certainly Plutarch.
At pp. 221-222 this important later Platonist has
his philosophical credentials challenged on silly grounds (and then his
inclusion is not defended), his status as a Roman philosopher cast quite
sensibly into doubt (and then never redeemed).
His inclusion in a book on Roman
philosophy could be justified on some conceptions of what Roman philosophy is,
but then we would expect to see a number of other Greek philosophers who worked
in Greek under Roman dominance as well.
After reading this one-dimensional and
limited discussion I found it hard to escape the conviction that Plutarch is
included because of his importance as a literary figure.
It is revealing that in
his preface (x) Morford confesses without shame that he has not bothered to read
the Moralia straight through before discussing Plutarch as a
philosopher.
Even more worrisome, unfortunately, is the amount of outdated scholarship
served up to the reader without warning and the volume of sheer misunderstanding
which Morford displays in many parts of the book.
That he should inflict error
on his audience is of course bad enough, but often the confusions have an effect
even on the external and biographical account which he (quite reasonably) set
out to provide.
A full catalogue of problems would be tedious -- and unfair as
well, since it would tend to mask the fact that there is valuable material in
the book.
But unfortunately most readers will not be able to distinguish the
good from the bad without an independent guide, so a few illustrations of where
things go wrong need to be given.
On p. 21 Morford mistranslates Aristotle (rhetoric is not the "answering
voice" to dialectic; antistrophos means "counterpart").
Later (pp. 24
ff.) Panaetius' important work peri kathêkontos is discussed as though
the De Officiis is the only source for it.
There is no sign of any
awareness of work by van Straaten, let alone Alesse.
This is puzzling, since, on
the principles which Morford apparently uses to include Plutarch, Panaetius and
Posidonius might well have been considered major Roman philosophers in their own
rights and so worthy of some basic research.
The banality of Morford's handling
of Panaetius is indicated by his statement (p. 26) that it "is significant that
he focused on the responsibility of human beings for their moral choices, a
doctrine in keeping with the traditional emphasis on individual initiative among
the Roman senatorial class".
This is no doubt true, but with whose views and
values does this significant idea stand in contrast?
It cannot be very
significant that Roman aristocrats would agree with Panaetius' focus on
responsibility if virtually everyone else did too.
A similar insensitivity turns up on p. 37, where we are told that Cicero's
"association with Diodotus meant that, despite being an Academic, he was
sympathetic to Stoic ethics, with their emphasis on virtue and reason."
The
presupposition seems to be that Academics weren't much inclined to emphasize
virtue and reason -- which would come as a surprise to almost anyone who has
read Plato, not just the professional philosophers whose interests Morford isn't
catering to.
Possibly Morford meant something less misguided, but this is all he
says on the matter.
This sloppiness is perhaps matched by what we read on p. 58.
"Cicero's discussion of the pathos of love is thin [in Tusculans
book 4], but he does consider the question of the Greek attitude towards
homosexual love (sections 70-72), once again proposing reason as an
alternative."
Given that the actual content of Tusculans 4 isn't
discussed, it is hard to know where to start in making sense of this seemingly
homophobic muddle.
There is much more of this sort.
For no particularly good reason Cicero's
De Republica is discussed out of its chronological order, seriously
disrupting the picture of Cicero's philosophical career.
Throughout his
discussion (pp. 69 ff.), which is full of approving paraphrase, Morford clearly
fails to understand the differences and similarities between Platonic and Stoic
ideas, which renders his account of influences on this complex and important
work useless.
On p. 81 Cotta is referred to as the principal speaker of
the De Natura Deorum rather than a principal speaker (Torquatus
may be a trivial Epicurean, but Balbus in book 2 certainly deserves to be
remembered.)
I should conclude my perhaps uncharitable litany of complaints with
an allusion to two passages which will do damage to inexperienced readers.
The
first is Morford's discussion of a suitable translation of officium in
the De Officiis (p. 89).
It is astonishing to me that he can recognize
the seriousness of the question, cite Dyck's thorough and sensible discussion
and his recommended translation ("appropriate action"), and then decide to keep
the misleading and old-fashioned term "duty" because it is "more familiar and
less cumbersome."
This borders on open contempt for good scholarship.
The second
passage is the discussion of Lucretius' arguments about the fear of death, which
plainly expresses open contempt for the value of philosophical argument.
On p.
119 Morford applauds the "ringing affirmation" nil igitur mors est ad nos
and then says that the rest of book 3 of De Rerum Natura, which he admits
contains the proofs for this important proposition, is "hardly
necessary."
Morford's book is not just one where the narrow interests of
professional philosophers are set aside in the interests of a biographical and
external account of Roman philosophy.
It seems at times to be a forum for the
author's active dislike for ideas and argument.
Morford too frequently relies on out-of-date scholarship.
Hence we find Varro
relying on the chimerical vetusta placita (p. 134) which, if it ever did
exist, certainly was not written by Aetius.
Two decades of serious research on
the development of doxography and the influence of Carneadean divisiones
on Roman thinkers have somehow escaped Morford.
Significant parts of Seneca are
unapologetically described as "diatribes" long after the use of this
pseudo-genre has become at least problematic.
Only someone who had never read
the De Beneficiis could say (p. 178) that much of its seven books is
summarized in Letter 81.
Most astonishing, perhaps, given Morford's
determination to see Roman philosophy through its impact on literary works,
especially poetry, Rosenmeyer's Senecan Drama and Stoic Cosmogony
(Berkeley 1989), which deals with Seneca's tragedies and their relationship to
his Stoicism is missing from the bibliography.
I have focussed on the negatives to support my general criticism.
The reader
should not conclude that there is not a good deal of value in this book.
Let me
just point to the argument on pp. 109-110 for the incompleteness of De Rerum
Natura.
Those who turn to this book already familiar with the subjects
treated and with the relevant scholarship will find the good bits easily enough.
The main risk is that the errors, anachronisms, and confusions might not stand
out clearly enough to help less expert readers to navigate around them.
Hence it
can only be recommended for the experienced and independent reader accustomed to
sifting the wheat from the chaff.
This is very unfortunate, for the aim of the
book is important and English-speaking readers need a book with the aims and
scope of Roman Philosophy.
Perhaps the saddest reflection I am left with
is that, given the economic realities of popular scholarly publishing, the
existence of this book makes it less likely that a really good treatment in
English of the theme will be published any time soon.
I hope I am wrong.
No comments:
Post a Comment