The Ancient Romans avoided Austin’s performative ‘I acclaim’ as unmanly and resorted to a well-known gesture to implicate it! Adfectus omnes languescant necesse est, nisi voce, vultu, totius prope habitu corporis inardescunt. The Roman forcefully manipulated his body in the act of persuading an addressee. The Roman utterer engages with his addressee. The Roman utterer *communicates* with his addressee. In turn the addressee is able to apply and convey his reaction back to the utterer. A Roman gesture becomes *prescribed* from the delivery of an initially one-off unconventional utterance. Since Roman rhetorical treatises repeatedly stress that the utterer should elicit with his body a specific emotional response from his addressee. A particularised gesture — pointing with the index finger — would from the one-off scenario, later bring home an initially particularised detail to his addressee. The public setting of the utterance provides ample opportunities for the utterer to point at various monuments and buildings in the vicinity. Another range of bodily gesturing involves mimicry. The particularised way in which Antoninus formed and moved his hand when beginning an argument. The emperor (or duce in general) and his responsive crowd behave quasi-contractually. An acclamation by an urban addressee, Antoninus notes, differs in kind from that used by a rustic addresssee. This observation coincides with the disparaging remarks that Antoninus makes about the delivery of provincials. The proper rhetoric, it would seem, is for Antoninus urban — i. e., Roman — rhetoric, as in the gesture of the right arm upheld and left concealed by Ottaviano at Prima Porta. For the utterer’s body to have emotional emotional on the addressee, the reasonable grounds of the one-off scenario suffice. Antonino is more effective when his addressee is *unaware* of the potential mysterious arsenal of rhetorical devices being used in persuasion. If the addressee recognises that certain gesture is aimed at persuasion, the addressee finds the utterer less persuasive. Apuleius cites Antonino when he adds to the overall characterization of his bungling Thelyphron by having him use a vulgar gesture that came naturally to him. The inept vulgar gesture by Thelyphron’s coincides with the expectation of any elite addressee who happened by chance to be in the crowd! Terence’s pointing, clenched fist, pudicitia gesture — are well-known fromreliable contexts, including illustrations. Antoninus recalls Frontone’s advice, don’t be a clown, alluding to the avoidance of the gesturing over-employed by comic actors and dancers in pantomime. The lack of voice amplification, a non-acoustical spaces, and milling crowds present special challenges to Antonino, who must rely on some intricate combination of fingers! On the other hand, by striking the chest with the clenched fist the utterer means grief or anger iin a natural and universal mode. Vitters told Sraffa that, for one, he does not recall ever having used this “natural” gesture himself, but then as Bulwer notes in Chirologia that what’s natural is natural to this or that upbringing. Christians, unlike Romans, do not perform this gesture properly, but are ‘wont mysteriously to mince this natural expression.’ So the gesture *is* ceteris paribus natural — for first-century Romans — but unnaturalised by the Christians! The rhetorical education provided by Fromyone to Antonino was put to use in well-known historical episodes. The counter-conversational move of the vocative acclamation — as in the euphemistic barbarism, ‘Euge’ — on behalf of the addressee exercises a powerful influence on the utterer.. As the Thesaurus Linguae Latinae notes, the performative use of ‘adclamare’ initially carries a sardonic implicature. The *site* for an acclamation ranges from the Forum or the Campus Martius to the circus, arena, or theater. The utterer’s response increases in frequency and becomes more positive in tone as its direct political implicature lessens — from a simple applause to a complex chanted phrase — as in Germanicus POxy. 25 2435r -. A give and take occurs whenever an utterer addressed a set of *Roman citizens* assembled as a mass. An emperor such as Tiberius — who changed the electorate rules — has a relationship with his crowd, determined by the crowd’s reaction which made it virtually obligatory for him to attend this or that game. The impact that public acclamations has on imperial policy is evidenced by the choice of which gladiator to display at a game to more crucial issues such as the price of grain and even his selection as emperor himself! The growing theatricalization of politics which reached its apex with Mussolini and Berlusconi, the flamboyance of gesture bemoaned by Cato the Censor and the increased importance of the acclamation are symptomatic of how the Roman utterer is perceived as a performer soliciting uptake — alla Austin — the roar of the paint, the smell of the crowd. Utterer and addressee are continually negotiating their interdependence. Especially interesting is the way in which the addresee’s reaction is endowed with a power to play a political role not only the utterer’s decision and but in the implementation of this or that policy. A. Vasaly, Representations: Images of the World in Ciceronian Oratory. R. Brilliant, Gesture and Rank in Roman Art. E. Gunderson, Discovering the Body in Roman Oratory,” in M. Wyke ed., Parchments of Gender. Deciphering the Bodies of Antiquity, Oxford, A. Corbeill, Thumbs in Ancient Rome: Pollex as Index, M. Atkinson, Our Masters’ Voices: the Language and Body Language of Politics; A. Funck, ” Accipiter, acclamatio, acclamo,” Archiv für lateinische Lexicographie und Grammatik. F. Millar, The Crowd in Rome in the Late Republic.
Wednesday, October 19, 2022
L’implicatura di Antonino
“All emotional appeals necessarily lose their force if they are not kindled by the voice, facial expression, and demeanor of practically the entire body” (Quint. Inst. 11.3.2: adfectus omnes languescant necesse est, nisi voce, vultu, totius prope habitu corporis inardescunt). With these words Quintilian introduces his thirty-odd pages on how the Roman orator can most forcefully manipulate the body in the act of persuading an audience. In this revised Michigan dissertation, Aldrete attempts to situate Quintilian’s assertion in a larger context and in so doing provide an analysis of the interaction between crowd and speaker in the late Republic and early Empire. The book falls into the two distinct halves indicated by the title, the first covering gestures in oratory, the second the context and function of acclamations from the crowd. A. sees these two forms of expression as the essential components of how the public speaker at Rome engaged with his hearers: “This work is a study of communication, how Roman speakers communicated with their audiences and how in turn audiences were able to apply and convey their reactions back to the speakers” (xvii).
Chapter One (3-43) surveys the prescriptions regarding gesture in Roman rhetorical treatises and, to the extent they can be reconstructed, their application in extant oratory. A. begins with a review of the importance placed upon delivery in the Greek and Roman rhetorical tradition and then turns to a selective overview of Quintilian’s detailed discussion of the topic ( Inst. 11.3). Since Roman rhetorical treatises repeatedly stress that the orator should elicit with his body specific emotional responses from his audience, A. is especially interested in how Quintilian’s descriptions are thought to complement the verbal appeals of a speaker. The next and longest section looks at places in extant oratory where the orator could have employed one specific gesture — pointing with the index finger — to bring home a particular detail to his audience. The discussion is necessarily speculative, but A. offers good observations about how the public setting of most speeches would have provided ample opportunities for the orator to point at various monuments and buildings in the vicinity. The bulk of the examples given, however, have less to do with the significance of the gesture — it is, after all, not the speaker’s index finger per se that evokes an emotional response — as with the orator’s use of place, a subject recently explored in greater detail by Ann Vasaly.1 The chapter concludes by considering other ways the orator could have used his body: in mimicry, in keeping time to his words, and in providing signals to the crowd.
This discussion of gesture assumes throughout that speaker and audience interacted according to “rules and at least a tacit agreement to abide by them” (xvii). A. does a good job of summarizing the rules (relying almost exclusively on the explicit testimony of Cicero and Quintilian), but he does not choose to speculate about the origins of this “tacit agreement.” How, for example, does Quintilian “know” the specific way in which Cicero formed and moved his hand when beginning his defense of Archias (which A. cites without comment on 15) or, even more interestingly, what causes him to believe he knows the gesture of Demosthenes at a specific point in a speech delivered over four hundred years earlier ( Inst. 11.3.97)? The elite orator and responsive crowd seem indeed to have made an agreement, but for what purpose and at whose expense is not a subject that this book chooses to address. A. does, however, cite evidence that may lead at least part way toward an answer when he notes in the second half of his book evidence to suggest that the acclamations of the urban plebs differed in kind from those used in rural Italy (130). A.’s observation here coincides with the disparaging remarks that Roman rhetorical treatises consistently make about the delivery of provincial orators. The proper rhetoric, it would seem, is urban rhetoric.
The second chapter (“Gesture in Roman Society;” 44-84) covers narrower ground than its title indicates, being restricted primarily to evidence outside of the rhetorical tradition that could indicate the familiarity of the average Roman with the detailed system offered by Quintilian. His consideration of artistic representations of Roman orators, largely dependent on Brilliant,2 includes only one example of a hand gesture (from the reconstructed right hand of the Prima Porta Augustus). Nevertheless, A. confidently concludes that the handbooks “accurately represented the everyday practice of Roman orators” (50), seemingly on the basis of statues that show speakers with right arm upraised and left concealed. A.’s further considerations of the extent to which the handbooks reflect daily practice are not much more satisfying. For the body to have emotional effect on the hearer, Aldrete assumes that the audience would need to have “knowledge” of systems such as Quintilian’s. Although this could seem an intuitive assumption, the existence of a system in use by speakers does not necessitate an awareness of this system on the part of an audience. Modern studies of crowd communication show that in fact speakers are more effective when the audience is unaware of the potential rhetoric being used in persuasion; when hearers recognize that certain gestures are aimed at persuasion, they find the speaker less persuasive.3 A.’s one concrete example of a member of the non-elite employing an oratorical gesture (Apul. Met. 2.21) can be shown to demonstrate that, on the contrary, the precise vocabulary of gesture was mysterious to the crowd (50). In this passage, Apuleius adds to the overall characterization of his bungling Thelyphron by having him use a gesture that is in fact notattested by Quintilian.4 Rather than revealing knowledge, Thelyphron’s inept oratory coincides with the expectations of Apuleius’ elite readers.
In the next section, A. ably treats the much-discussed topic of the illustrated manuscripts of Terence. His conclusion that the illustrations “make many of the convoluted descriptions in Quintilian intelligible” (67) is again unfortunately overstated, since nearly all the gestures he discusses in this section — pointing, clenched fist, “pudicitia” gesture — are well-known from more reliable contexts than these illustrations, whose date and relevance to antiquity — not to mention to ancient oratory — are much disputed. In this section, as elsewhere, A. assumes on unclear grounds that the gestures employed by comic actors, dancers in pantomime, and orators belong to comparable systems (57; see too 51-52, 77). The chapter concludes with interesting and useful observations on the place of gesture in ancient Rome, where lack of voice amplification, non-acoustical spaces, and milling crowds presented special challenges to the public speaker. I doubt however that gestures can really “be seen at a greater range than words can be heard” (82); can intricate combinations of fingers really be read at such a distance, which A. estimates at 65 meters? The passage from Plutarch ( Pomp.25) cited in support is not strictly relevant, since here the speaker uses gesture not to overcome distance but to be understood over crowd noise, and the gestures required would hardly need to be complex (pace A.). A. certainly demonstrates in these opening chapters the importance of gesture to the Roman orator, but I am not as comfortable with his claims about how these gestures were construed by those members of the crowd not learned in rhetorical theory.
As is clear from my summary so far, Aldrete is committed to showing bodies in action and not to interrogating the texts that describe those bodies. As a result, do not expect from this book any engagement with the many recent works analyzing constructions of the body in antiquity. A. accepts readily Quintilian’s notions of the natural body and is not concerned with how the rhetorician’s emphasis on the capacity of the hand and gesture to persuade succeeds in creating a realm of the unnatural, into which fall — to name the most common categories — non-Romans, actors, and effeminate men.5 In fact, A. seems comfortable himself in ascribing certain gestures to an unexplained “nature.” Striking the chest with the clenched fist to denote grief or anger is described as seeming “natural and almost universal” (9). He has not chosen to consider instead whether Quintilian is here constructing the natural and that the construction survives as natural today because of direct transmission from Quintilian via rhetorical treatises, acting manuals, and staged melodrama. I, for one, do not recall ever having used this “natural” gesture myself, but then I found in Bulwer’s Chirologia of 1644 (a work which owes much to Quintilian) that the explanation for this lack comes from my upbringing: Roman Catholics do not perform the gesture properly, but “are wont … mysteriously to mince this natural expression” (75). So the gesture isnatural — for first-century Romans and seventeenth-century Anglicans. Despite these reservations — and to stop criticizing A. for a book he did not write —, the first half of Gestures and Acclamations in Ancient Romeperforms a useful service in bringing together much of the evidence needed to assess the use of an orator’s body in persuading his audience.
Chapter Three (85-97), on “Oratory and the Roman Emperors,” provides a nice bridge between the two halves of the book. Here A. briefly surveys what we know about the rhetorical education of the earliest emperors and then recounts specific historical episodes which indicate the importance the emperors placed on their interaction with the people.
With Chapters Four and Five (101-127 and 128-164; confusingly referred to as Chapters Three and Four in the Introduction xx-xxi), A. shifts his focus to the orator’s audience, wishing to show that acclamations on behalf of the crowd could exercise a powerful influence on individual politicians, especially emperors. The discussion starts out unpromising with a citation of the definition that the Oxford Latin Dictionary provides for acclamo and acclamatio. Consultation of Thesaurus Linguae Latinae would have offered not only a more nuanced examination of the words, but also one more in keeping with A.’s subsequent discussion. As Funck notes in the article cited in TLL, the words acclamo and acclamatio have quite a different development from what OLD implies. They are in fact rarely neutral, and the negative connotations that they originally could possess have largely disappeared by the time of the empire.6 This semantic study supports well A.’s interesting analysis of how the site of acclamations and crowd/politician interaction moves from the politically charged spaces of the Forum and Campus Martius during the republic and into venues for entertainment such as the circus, arena, and theater. Crowd response increases in frequency and becomes more positive in tone as its direct political implications lessen. After offering a convenient typology of the acclamation — they range from simple applause to chanted phrases of surprising complexity —, A. makes fine use of the fragmentary speech of Germanicus delivered at Alexandria (POxy. 25 [1959] 2435r) to demonstrate the extraordinary give and take that must often have occurred whenever a speaker addressed Roman citizens assembled as a mass (115-118).
The different relationships emperors had with the crowd and how crowd reactions determined these relationships is the primary focus of these pages. Although often repetitive (for example, we are reminded on numerous occasions of the frequent opportunities for plebs/emperor interaction, and on pages 150 and 156 similar points are made about the electoral changes made under Tiberius) and although assertion occasionally replaces proof (e.g., the compulsion for emperors to attend games, which “seems … quite strong” on 120 becomes “obligatory” by 156), A. is at his best here in citing ancient evidence for the impact that public acclamations could have on imperial action, from the relatively trivial choice of which gladiator to display at the games, to more crucial issues such as the price of grain and even the selection of the emperor himself.
In the “Conclusion” (165-171), A. links his overall theme of gesture and acclamation with the well-worn theme of how the transition from republic to empire witnessed a growing theatricalization of politics: the flamboyance of gesture bemoaned by Quintilian and the increased importance of acclamation are symptomatic of how the public speaker has come to be perceived as more performer than orator. A helpful index of terms closes the book. I would like to have seen also an index locorum.
Despite its unevenness, Gestures and Acclamations in Ancient Rome offers many individual insights into the ways in which the crowd and speaker were continually negotiating their interdependence. Especially interesting are the ways in which crowd reactions could play a role not only in individual decisions but in the creation of policy. Here lies, I think, the importance of A.’s work, in its attempt to extend into the empire the kind of revisionist views of the populace that has informed recent discussions of the political power of the crowd during the republic.7
Notes
1. A. Vasaly, Representations: Images of the World in Ciceronian Oratory (Berkeley 1993).
2. R. Brilliant, Gesture and Rank in Roman Art(New Haven 1963) = Memoirs of the Connecticut Academy of Arts and Sciences 14.
3. For this type of approach, see E. Gunderson, “Discovering the Body in Roman Oratory,” in M. Wyke ed., Parchments of Gender. Deciphering the Bodies of Antiquity (Oxford 1998) 169-189.
4. A. Corbeill, “Thumbs in Ancient Rome: Pollex as Index,” MAAR 42 (1997) 7.
5. E.g., M. Atkinson, Our Masters’ Voices: the Language and Body Language of Politics (New York 1984) (a work cited in A.’s bibliography).
6.A. Funck, ” Accipiter, acclamatio, acclamo,” Archiv für lateinische Lexicographie und Grammatik 9 (1896) 589-591.
7. See especially F. Millar, The Crowd in Rome in the Late Republic (Ann Arbor 1998) for a full discussion of the issue and previous bibliography.
Friday, October 14, 2022
Enea: il primo stoico
STOICISM IN ROMAN HISTORY AND LITERATURE. ALTHOUGH up to this point it has been our main
Spread of | Purpose to set forth the doctrines of Stoicism, Stoicisa.: we have seen incidentally that these came to exercise a wide influence in Roman society, and that the later teachers are far less occupied in the attainment of truth than in the right guidance of disciples who lean upon them. In the present chapter we propose to describe more particularly the practical influence of Stoicism. Our information, whether drawn from history or from poetry, refers generally to the upper classes of Roman society ; as to the influence of the sect amongst the poor we have no sufficient record. But although it is very generally held that the Stoics made no effort to reach the working classes of Rome, or met with no success in that direction’, the evidence points rather to an opposite conclusion, at any rate as regards all that development of the system which was coloured by Cynism, the philosophy of the poor®. Our actual records are therefore rather of the nature of side-lights upon the system ; the main stream of Stoic influence may well have flowed in courses with which we are imperfectly acquainted, and its workings may perhaps come to light first in a period of history which lies beyond our immediate scope. 1 Lightfoot, Phzlippzans, p. 319; Dill, Roman Soctety, p. 334; Warde Fowler, Social Life at Rome, p. 27. 2 The practice of street-preaching, as described by Horace and Epictetus, points this way; and the world-wide diffusion of Stoicism, in more or less diluted forms, is hardly reconcileable with its restriction to a single class of society. Individual Romans who professed themselves disciples Deeg of the Porch owed their allegiance to the sect to direct and two causes, in varying proportion. On the one hand aie they had attended lectures or private instruction given by eminent Stoic teachers, or had immersed themselves in Stoic literature. This influence was in almost all cases the influence of Greek upon Roman, and the friendship between the Stoic Panaetius and Scipio Aemilianus was the type of all subsequent discipleship. Scipio himself did not perhaps formally become a Stoic, but he introduced into Roman society the atmosphere of Stoicism, known to the Romans as humanitas: this included an aversion to war and civil strife, an eagerness to appreciate the art and literature of Greece, and an admiration for the ideals depicted by Xenophon, of the ruler in Cyrus, and of the citizen in Socrates*. All the Stoic nobles of the time of the republic are dominated by these feelings. On the other hand individuals were often attracted by the existence of a society which proclaimed itself independent of the will of rulers, and offered its members mutual support and consolation. Such men were often drawn into Stoicism by the persuasion of friends, without being necessarily well-grounded in philosophical principle; and in this way small groups or cliques might easily be formed in which social prejudice or political bias outweighed the formal doctrine of the school. Such a group was that of the ‘old Romans’ of the first century of the principate; and with the spread of Stoicism this indirect and imperfect method of attachment constantly grows in importance as compared with direct discipleship. Of the first group of Roman Stoics the most notable The Scipionic Was C. LAELIUS, the intimate friend of Scipio, SHS Ec who became consul in 140 B.C. In his youth he had listened to the teaching of Diogenes of Babylon, in later life he was the friend of Panaetius*. He was in his time a 3 *semper Africanus Socraticum Xenophontem in manibus habebat’ Cic. TZesc. disp. ii 26, 62; ‘Cyrus ille a Xenophonte ad effigiem iusti imperi scriptus...quos quidem libros Africanus de manibus ponere non solebat’ ad Quznt. 11 8, 23. 4 116 [Laelius] qui Diogenem Stoicum adulescens, post autem Panaetium audi- erat’ Fiz. ii 8, 24. — notable orator with a quiet flowing style®; his manners were cheerful®, his temper was calm’; and, as we have seen’, he seemed to many the nearest of all the Romans to the ideal of the Stoic sage. He is brought on as the chief speaker in Cicero’s de Amicitia. Another close friend of Africanus was Sp. MUMMIUS, the brother of the conqueror of Achaia; his oratory was marked by the ruggedness characteristic of the Stoic school®. Passing mention may be made of L. FURIUS PHILUS, consul in 136 B.C, and a member of the same group, though his philosophical views are not known to us”. From the ‘humane’ movement sprang the GracchanThe Gracchan reforms, which al! alike aimed at deposing from pened power the class to which the reformers by birth belonged. To the temper of mind which made such a desire possible Stoic doctrine had largely contribute. The Greeks had taught their Roman pupils to see in the nascent Roman empire, bearing the watchword of the ‘majesty of the Roman name’ (smatestas nominis Romant), at least an approximation to the ideal Cosmopolis: and many Romans so far responded to this suggestion as to be not unfriendly towards plans for extending their citizenship and equalizing the privileges of those who enjoyed it. C. BLOssIUS of Cumae, a pupil of Antipater of Tarsus, went so far as to instigate Tiberius Gracchus to the schemes which proved his destruction"; whilst other Stoics, equally sincere in their aims, disagreed with the violence shown by Tiberius in his choice of method. Amongst the latter was Q. AELIUS TUBERO, a nephew of Africanus”, who became consul in 118 B.c. He devoted himself day and night to the > “lenitatem Laelius habuit’ Cic. de Or. iii 7, 28; “Ὁ. Laelius et P. Africanus imprimis eloquentes’ Braz. 21, 82. 6 ‘in C. Laelio multa hilaritas’ Of. i 30, 108. 7 *praeclara est aequabilitas in omni vita et idem semper vultus eademque frons, ut de Socrate itemque de C. Laelio accepimus’ 24. 26, go. 8 See above, § 326. 9 «Sp. [Mummius] nihilo ornatior, sed tamen astrictior; fuit enim doctus ex disciplina Stoicorum’ Cic. Brut. 25, 94. 10 “non tulit ullos haec civitas humanitate politiores P. Africano, C. Laelio, L. Furio, qui secum eruditissimos homines ex Graecia palam semper habuerunt’ de Or. ii 37, 154. 1 Cic. Amic. 11, 37. 15. «Ti. Gracchum a Q. Tuberone aequalibusque amicis derelictum videbamus’ 2d. Sip ecrelldl aA yay Ie ? es σῦν, | we he study of philosophy”, and though of no mark as an orator, won himself respect by the strictness and consistency of his life™, Panaetius, Posidonius, and Hecato all addressed treatises to him”; and he is a leading speaker in Cicero’s Republic. After the fall of the Gracchi the Stoic nobles con- Laclius το tittued to play distinguished and honourable parts | eeGU NEE, in public life. A family succession was main- : tained through two daughters of Laelius, so that here we may perhaps recognise the beginning of the deservedly famous ‘Stoic marriages. Of the two ladies the elder was married to — Q. MUcIUS SCAEVOLA, known as ‘the augur,’ who was consul in 117 B.c. He was a devoted friend of Panaetius, and famous for his knowledge of civil law’. The younger daughter was married to C. FANNIUS, who obtained some distinction as a historian”. In C. LUCILIUS we find the Latin poet of Stoicism ; the views which he expresses in his satires on religion and ethics are in the closest agreement with the teaching of Panaetius™, and the large circulation of his poems must have diffused them through wide circles’. At the same time his attacks on the religious institu- tions of Numa and his ridicule of his own childish beliefs may well have brought philosophy into ill odour as atheistic and unpatriotic: and we find the statesmen of the next generation specially anxious to avoid any such imputations. A dominating figure is that of Ὁ. MUCIUS SCAEVOLA, Scaevola‘the COmmonly called ‘the pontifex, who was a nephew pontifex.’ of his namesake mentioned above, and derived from him his interest in civil law; he was consul in 95 B.C. He overcame the difficulty about the popular religion by distin- τ ale Of ΠΔ 28%, δὴ- 14 *quoniam Stoicorum est facta mentio, Q. Aelius Tubero fuit illo tempore, nullo in oratorum numero, sed vita severus et congruens cum ea disciplina quam colebat ’ Brut. 31, 117. 15 Fin. iv 9, 23; Off. ili 15, 63. 16 ‘ Panaetii illius tui’ Cic. de Or. 1 11, 45; ‘[Mucius augur] oratorum in numero non fuit: iuris civilis intellegentia atque omni prudentiae genere praestitit’ Brut. 26, 102. 7 <C, Fannius, C. Laeli gener,...instituto Laelii Panaetium audiverat. eius omnis in dicendo facultas ex historia ipsius non ineleganter scripta perspici potest’ 2b. 101. 38 Schmekel, A@ittlere Stoa, pp. 444, 445. 19 See especially his praise of virtue, beginning ‘virtus, Albine, est pretium per- solvere verum | queis in versamur, queis vivimu’ rebu’ potesse’ fr. 1. neice, — guishing on Stoic lines three classes of deities, (i) mythical deities, celebrated by the poets with incredible and unworthy narrations”; (ii) philosophical deities, better suited for the schools than for the market-place; (iii) civic deities, whose ceremonies it is the duty of state officials to maintain™, interpreting them so as to agree with the philosophers rather than with the poets”. In this spirit he filled the position of chief officer of the state religion. He was however no time-server ; for being appointed after his consulship to be governor of Asia, he joined with his former quaestor P. RUTILIUS RUFUS in the design of repressing the extortion of the pudblicanz. A decisive step taken by him was to declare all dishonourable contracts invalid; and more than a generation later his just and sparing administration was gratefully remembered both at Rome and in the provinces*. The eguz¢es took their revenge not on Scaevola but on Rutilius®, whom they brought to trial in 92 B.C., when Scaevola pleaded his cause in a simple and dignified way that became a Stoic, but did not exclude some traces of elegance™. He is regarded as the father of Roman law, for he was the first to codify it, which he did in eighteen volumes”. He also wrote a special work on definitions, which no doubt reflected the interest which the Stoics took in this part of logic. It seems beyond dispute that the systematic study The Stoic. Of law, which developed in later centuries into lawyers. the science of Roman jurisprudence, and as such has exercised a weighty influence on the development of Western civilisation, had its beginnings amongst a group of men profoundly influenced by Stoic teaching. It does not 20 «primum genus [poéticum] nugatorium dicit [Scaevola] esse, quod multa de dis fingantur indigna’ Aug. Czv. De. iv 27, on the authority of Varro. "1 ¢tertium genus’ inquit Varro ‘quod in urbibus cives, maxime sacerdotes, nosse atque administrare debent’ Aug. Czv. De. vi 5. 22 «maior societas nobis debet esse cum philosophis quam cum poetis’ 2d. 6. 38. “ego habeo [exceptionem] tectiorem ex Q. Mucii P. F. edicto Asiatico; extra quam si tta negotium gestum est, ut co Stari non oporteat ex fide bona; multaque sum secutus Scaevolae’ Cic. Azz. vi 1, 15. *4 ‘hanc gloriam iustitiae et abstinentiae fore inlustriorem spero.. quod Scaevolae contigit? 2d. v 17, 5. 25 See above, § 326. 6 <dixit causam illam quadam ex parte Q. Mucius, more suo, nullo adparatu, pure et dilucide’ Cic. de Or. i 53, 229; ‘Scaevola parcorum elegantissimus’ Avzt. 40, 148. 27 Ὁ Mucius pontifex maximus ius civile primus constituit, generatim ia libros XVIII redigendo’ Pompon. Dzg. i 2, 2, 41. — therefore follow that the fundamental ideas expressed by such terms as 22,5. gentium, lex naturae, are exclusively Stoic in origin. The former phrase appears to have been in common use at this time to indicate the laws generally in force amongst the peoples that surrounded Rome; the latter is a philosophical term derived from the Greek, denoting an ideal law which ought to exist amongst men everywhere*. The principle of obedience to nature is not peculiar to the Stoic philosophy, but belongs to the | common substratum of all philosophical thought. It does however seem to be the case that the Stoic theory of the ‘common law’ (κοινὸς νόμος) was in fact the stimulus which enabled the Romans to transform their system of ‘rights, gradually throwing over all that was of the nature of mechanical routine or caste privilege, and harmonizing contradictions by the principle of fairness: The successor of Scaevola was C. AQUILIUS GALLUS, praetor in 66 B.C. with Cicero, of whom it is specially noted that he guided his exposition of law by the principle of equity”; and after him . SULPICIUS RUFUS, the contemporary and intimate friend of Cicero. We do not know that he was a Stoic, but he was a student of dialectic under L. LUCILIUS BALBUS, who as well as his brother belonged to this school®; and he followed Stoic principles in studying oratory just enough to make his exposition clear#. He was the acknowledged head of his profession, and compiled 180 books on law®. In the civil war he took sides with Caesar*. Amongst men of high rank definitely pledged to Stoics of the Stoicism in the generation preceding Cicero are Seo mutter ELMS) SAILO (Cites 1, πὶ ΒΘ swho devoted himself to Roman grammar and antiquities, and was *S Ἢ, Nettleship, Zs Gentiwm (Journal of Philology xiii 26, pp. 169 sqq.). °9 “qui iuris civilis rationem nunquam ab aequitate seiunxerit’ Cic. Caec. 27, 78. 30 « C. Aquilio Gallo’ Brit. 42, 1543 cf. de Orat. iii 21, 78. 31 ¢ Servius [mihi videtur] eloquentiae tantum assumpsisse, ut ius civile facile possit tueri’ Brut. 40, 150. *2 <[Servius] longe omnium in iure civili princeps’ 7. 41, 151: Pomp. Dzg. i 2, 2, 43. 33 For an interesting account of his career and death see Warde Fowler, Socéa/ Life at Rome, pp. 118-121. 34 ‘idem Aelius Stoicus esse voluit’ Cic. Brztes 56, 206. A. 25 cum discendi causa duobus peritissimis operam dedisset, L. Lucilio Balbo et _ — the teacher of both Cicero and Varro; Q. LUCILIUS BALBUS, whose knowledge of this philosophy rivalled that of his Greek teachers”, and who is the exponent of the Stoic view in Cicero’s de Natura Deorum, the scene of which takes us back to about 76 B.C.; SEXTUS POMPEIUS, uncle of Pompey the Great, and distinguished both as a philosopher and as a jurist®*; and more particularly P. RUTILIUS RUFUS, to whom we have already referred”. A pupil and devoted admirer of Panaetius*, a trained philosopher**, and a sound lawyer*, he brought his career at Rome to an abrupt end by his firm resistance to the publicant, as already recounted*. With true cosmopolitanism he retired to Smyrna, and accepted the citizenship of that town. His stern principles did not prevent him from saving his life in the massacre ordered by Mithradates, by assuming Greek dress”; the massacre itself was the ripe fruit of the abuses which he had endeavoured to repress. He is one of the characters in Cicero’s de Republica. Of the Stoics of Cicero’s time the most eminent was | M. Porcius CATO (95-48 B.c.). In him Stoicism received a special colouring by association with the traditions of ancient Roman manners. In his early years he became a pupil of Antipater of Tyre*, and so far adopted the Cynic ideal as to train himself for public life by freely submitting to hunger, cold, and hardship“. After a period of service in the army he made a journey to Asia to secure the companionship of Athenodorus the elder*. He became a practised speaker; and though he adhered firmly to the Stoic tradition of plain language and short sentences“, yet could become eloquent on the great Cato. 3° Ὁ, Lucilius Balbus tantos progressus habebat in Stoicis, ut cum excellentibus in eo genere Graecis compararetur’ JV. D. i 6, 15. 36 * Sextus frater praestantissimum ingenium contulerat ad summam iuris civilis et rerum Stoicarum scientiam’ Brudus 47, 175. a See § 2.n7- 8 *Posidonius scribit P. Rutilium dicere solere, quae Panaetius praetermisisset, propter eorum quae fecisset praestantiam neminem esse persecutum’ Cic. Of iii 2, Io. 89 «TP. Rutilius], doctus vir et Graecis litteris eruditus, prope perfectus in Stoicis’ Brutus 30, 114. 40 “multa praeclara de iure’ 2. 41 See above, § 326. 42 Cic. pro Rabir. το, 27. 43 Plut. Cato minor 4, τ. > 4) 2 Wy By Bo 2 WO; τῶν τὶ 46 «Cato perfectus, mea sententia, Stoicus,...in ea est haeresi, quae nullum sequi- tur florem orationis neque dilatat argumentum; sed minutis interrogatiunculis, quasi punctis, quod proposuit efficit” Cic. Par. Pro. 2. — themes of his philosophy”, and could win the approval of the people even for its paradoxes*. He was resolutely opposed to bribery and extortion. As quaestor in B.C. 66 he introduced reform into the public finances, and put an end to embezzlements by officials. His popularity became very great, and he was elected tribune of the plebs towards the end of the year 63 B.C., when his voice decided the senators to decree the death of the associates of Catiline. With his subsequent policy Cicero finds fault, because Cato refused to connive at the extortions of the publicant: and from Cicero’s criticisms has arisen the accepted view that Cato was an unpractical statesman. On the other hand it may weil be held that if the Roman aristocracy had included more men like Cato, the republic might have been saved: and towards the end of his life Cicero bitterly lamented that he had not sufficiently valued the sincere friendship which Cato offered him®. In the year 54 B.c. the candidates for the office of tribune paid him a singular compliment; each deposited with him a large sum of money, which he was to forfeit if in Cato’s opinion he was guilty of bribery”. His whole political life was guided by the strictest moral principle”; even in so _ unimportant a matter as Cicero’s request for a triumph he would | do nothing to oblige a friend™. In private life he attempted to put into practice the principle of the community of women taught in Zeno’s Republic. He had married Marcia, daughter of Philippus, and had three children by her: in 56 B.c. he gave her up to his. friend C. Hortensius, whose family was in danger of becoming extinct: finally on the threatening of the civil war in B.C. 50 he took her back to his own home. At a time when the marriage bond was lightly treated by many of his contemporaries he at least rose above petty motives. In the civil 47 *Cato dumtaxat de magnitudine animi, de morte, de omni laude virtutis, Stoice solet, oratoriis ornamentis adhibitis, dicere’ Cic. Pay. Pro. 3. 48 “animadverti Catonem...dicendo consequi ut illa [=loci graves ex philosophia] populo probabilia viderentur’ 2d. 1. #9 “Tdoleo] plus apud me simulationem aliorum quam [Catonis] fidem valuisse’ ad Alt. iil 15, 2 (in 8.6. 48). GW is τὰν Ti Fe °l *Catoni vitam ad certam rationis normam dirigenti et diligentissime perpendenti, momenta officiorum omnium’ JZ. 2, 3. 52 Cato apud Cic. ad Fam. xv 5, 2. .25--2 — war he took sides strongly against Caesar, his old political opponent. His self-sought death after Pharsalia won him a distinction which he had earned better by his life: and the unmeasured praise bestowed upon him a century later is perhaps due more to political bias than to philosophical respect®. The few words with which Virgil honours his memory are more effective, when he pictures Cato as chosen to be a judge in the world of the blest. Cato represents the Stoic view as to the summum bonum in Cicero’s de Finibus. Contemporary with Cicero and Cato was M. TERENTIUS Varro, Brutus WARRO (B.C; 116-28). In’ his) publicicareer same
god orci a political principles he was not unlike Cato; in his literary activity he more resembled Cicero. Both Varro and Cicero were deeply influenced by Stoic teaching, but as they were by no means professed adherents of this philosophy™, they may be here passed by. In, the) next) @ceneration M. JUNIUS BRUTUS (85-42 B.C.) concerns us more: for by his marriage with PORCIA, Cato’s daughter and an ardent Stoic, he came into a family connexion with the sect, with which his personal views, as we have seen, were not entirely in agreement™. Still Brutus was not altogether unfitted to play the part of Cato’s successor ; he was no mean orator”, and wrote more than one philosophical treatise®; whilst Cicero dedicated several of his philosophical works to him®. But the practical Stoicism of Porcia, who stabbed herself in the thigh to show that she was fit to be trusted with a political secret, shines out more brightly than the speculations of her husband. In her honour Martial 53 See for instance below, § 441, note 94. 54 ‘his [sc. piis] dantem iura Catonem’ Verg. Aez. viii 670. % <illam ᾿Ακαδημικήν...Δ Varronem transferamus: etenim sunt ᾿Αὐτιόχεια, quae iste valde probat’ Cic. “1270. xiii 12, 3; ‘in iis quae erant contra ἀκαταληψίαν praeclare collecta ab Antiocho, Varroni dedi;...aptius esse nihil potuit ad id philosophiae genus, quo ille maxime mihi delectari videtur’ 2b. 19, 3 and 5. 56 See above, § 123. ὅ7 ‘tu, [Brute,] qui non linguam modo acuisses exercitatione dicendi, sed et ipsam eloquentiam locupletavisses graviorum artium instrumento’ Cic. Brutus 97, 331. °8 ¢ Brutus in eo libro quem de virtute composuit’’ Sen. Dza/. xii 9, 4; ‘ Brutus in eo libro quem περὶ καθήκοντος inscripsit, dat multa praecepta’ 32. 95, 45. There was also a treatise de patientia. ; ὅ9 The de Finibus, de Natura Deorum, and Tusculanae disputationes. — has written one of the few epigrams in which he allows himself to be caught in a mood of admiration: yet his story of Porcia’s death must be rejected as unhistorical®, After the death of Brutus Stoicism ceases for a while to play a prominent part in Roman history; but its indirect influence is very marked in the two great / poets of the Augustan epoch, Horace and Virgil. Of these HORACE is in the main an Epicurean, and as such is quite entitled to use the Stoic paradoxes as matter for ridicule, and even to anticipate dangerous consequences from their practical application™. But in fact his works show a constantly increasing appreciation of the ethics of Stoicism. He recognises the high ideals and civic activity of its professors”, and he draws a noble picture of the Stoic sage, confident in his convictions, and bidding defiance to the crowd and the tyrant alike®. Of that practical wisdom and genial criticism which has made Horace the favourite poet of so many men eminent in public life, no small part consists of Stoic principles deftly freed from the paradoxical form in which they were conveyed to professed adherents. Horace. 433. With this picture of Stoicism seen from without we must contrast that given us by VIRGIL, who inherited the Stoic tradition from Aratus®, his model for the Georgics. Virgil's mind is penetrated by Stoic feeling, and his | works are an interpretation of the universe in the Stoic sense ; but like so many of his contemporaries he holds aloof from formal adherence to the sect, and carefully avoids its technical language. Quite possibly too he incorporated in his system elements drawn from other philosophies. In physics he accepts the principle that the fiery aether is the source of all life®; it is identical with the divine spirit® and the all-informing mind”. From this standpoint he is led on to the doctrine of purgatory®, Virgil. 50 Mart. Zp. 1 42. 6i See above, ὃ 374, note 66. 62 “nunc agilis fio et mersor civilibus undis, | virtutis verae custos rigidusque satelles’ 22. i 1, τό and 17. 63 See above, § 316, note 96. 64 See above, § go. 65 «joneus est ollis vigor et caelestis origo | seminibus’ “1672. vi 730, 731- 66 ‘caelum et terras | spiritus intus alit’ 26. 724, 726. 67 © totamque infusa per artus | mens agitat molem’ 74. 726, 727. 68 See above, §§ 295 to 297. — and from that he looks forward to the time of the conflagration, when all creation will be reconciled by returning to its primitive unity in the primal fire-spirit®. Still Virgil’s picture must be regarded rather as an adaptation than as an exposition of Stoicism ; it lacks the sharp outlines and the didactic tone of the poetry of Cleanthes or Lucretius, and other interpretations are by no means excluded. With the problem of the government of the universe Virgil's Virgil’s mind is occupied throughout the dened. theology. He is constantly weighing the relative importance of the three forces, fate, the gods, and fortune, precisely as the philosophers do. To each of the three he assigns a part in the affairs of men; but that taken by fate is unmistakably predominant. The individual gods have very little importance in the poem; they are to a large extent allegorical figures, representing human instincts and passions; they cannot divert destiny from its path, though with their utmost effort they may slightly delay its work or change its incidence. Above all these little gods Jove towers aloft, a power magnificent and munificent; at his voice the gods shudder and the worlds obey. But the power of Jove rests upon his complete acceptance of the irrevocable decrees of fate”. The critic may even describe him as a puppet- king, who wears an outward semblance of royalty, but is really obedient to an incessant interference from a higher authority. Virgil however appears truly to hold the Stoic principle that Fate and Jove are one; he thus takes us at once to the final problem of philosophy, the reconciliation of the conceptions of Law formed on the one hand by observing facts (the modern ‘Laws of Nature’) and on the other hand by recognising the moral instinct (the modern ‘Moral Law’). As we have seen, a reconciliation of these two by logic is intrinsically impossible. Virgil however shows us how they may be in practice reconciled by a certain attitude of mind; and because that attitude is one of resignation to and cooperation with the supreme power, it 9 *donec longa dies, perfecto temporis orbe, | concretam exemit labem, purumque reliquit | aetherium sensum atque aurai simplicis ignem’ «1671. vi 745 to 747. 70 “desine fata deum flecti sperare precando’ 20. 376. — would seem right to place Virgil by the side of Cleanthes as one of the religious poets of Stoicism. Virgil’s conception of ethics is displayed in the character Virgil's of Aeneas. Much modern criticism revolts against ethics: the character of Aeneas exactly as it does against that of Cato, and for the same reason, that it is without sympathy for Stoic ethics. To understand Aeneas we must first picture a man whose whole soul is filled by a reverent regard for destiny and submission to Jove, who represents destiny on its personal side. He can therefore never play the part of the hero in revolt ; but at the same time he is human, and liable to those petty weaknesses and aberrations from which even the sage is not exempt. He can hesitate or be hasty, can love or weep; but the sovereignty of his mind is never upset. In a happy phrase Virgil sums up the whole ethics of Stoicism : ~ ‘Calm in his soul he abides, and the tears roll down, but in vain*!.’ In contrast to Aeneas stands Dido, intensely human and passionate, and in full rebellion against her destiny. She is to him Eve the temptress, Cleopatra the seducer; but she is not destined to win a final triumph. A modern romance would doubtless have a different ending. Amongst writers who adopted much of the formal teaching of Stoicism without imbibing its spirit we may reckon OVID (43 B.C.-18 A.D.). Not only does he accept the central idea of Stoicism, that it is the divine fire by virtue of which every man lives and moves”, but he opens his greatest work by a description of the creation™ which appears to follow Stoic lines, and in which the erect figure of man is specially recognised as the proof of the pre-eminence which Providence has assigned to him over all the other works of the Creator“. But the tales related in the Wetamorphoses show no Ovid. 71 ‘mens immota manet; lacrimae volvuntur inanes’ Aez. iv 449; the ‘lacrimae inanes’ indicate the ruffling of the soul, in which the intelligence and will take no part. 7 “est deus in nobis: agitante calescimus illo’ Ov. 7. vi 5. 3 “ante mare et terras, et quod tegit omnia caelum, | unus erat toto Naturae vultus in orbe, | quem dixere Chaos, etc.’ 7762. i 5 to 88. 74 ¢os homini sublime dedit, caelumque tueri | iussit, et erectos ad sidera tollere vultus’ 24. 85 and 86. — trace of the serious religious purpose οἵ Virgil; and the society pictured in Ovid’s love poems gives only a caricature of the Stoic doctrines of the community of women, the absence of jealousy, and outspokenness of speech. Finally the plaintive tone of the Z7zstza shows how little Ovid was in touch with Stoic self-control amidst the buffetings of fortune. In the time of the next princeps we first find Gremuatias Stoicism associated with an unsympathetic. atti- conus: tude towards the imperial government. There was nothing in Stoic principles to suggest this opposition. Tiberius himself had listened to the teaching of the Stoic Nestor, and the simplicity of his personal life and the gravity of his manners might well have won him the support of sincere philosophers. But if Stoicism did not create the spirit of opposition, it confirmed it where it already existed. The memory of Cato associated Stoic doctrines with republican views: vague idealisations of Brutus and Cassius suggested the glorification of tyrannicide. CREMUTIUS CORDUS (ob. A.D. 25) had offended Seianus by a sarcastic remark: for when Tiberius repaired the theatre of Pompey, and the senate voted that a statue of Seianus should be erected there, Cordus said that this meant really spoiling the theatre”. Seianus then dropped a hint to his client Satrius, who accused Cordus before the senate of writing a history in which he highly praised Brutus, and declared Cassius to have been ‘the last of the Romans. A word of apology would have saved the life of Cordus; he resolved to die by his own act”, to the great annoyance of his prosecutors”. From this time on suicide became an object of political ambition. The Stoic tradition continued in the family of Cordus, and to his daughter Marcia, as a fellow-member of the sect, Seneca addressed the well-known Consolatio™,; but the title of ‘old Romans’ 7 ©exclamavit Cordus tunc vere theatrum perire’ Sen. Dad. vi 22, 4. 76 Tac. Ann. iv 34. Tacitus entirely ignores the personal motives underlying the story, and quite unnecessarily suggests that Tiberius was adopting the policy of repressing freedom of historical narration. 77 “accusatores queruntur mori Cordum’ Sen. Dead. vi 22, 7. 78 That Cremutius Cordus was a professed Stoic seems a fair inference from the story as a whole, and yet, as in several similar cases, is not expressly stated. — describes far better the true leanings of the men of whom Cordus was the forerunner. In the reign of Gaius (Caligula) we first find philoso ieee phers as such exposed to persecution ; and we may yalins: infer that, like the Jews, they resisted tacitly or openly the claim of the emperor to be worshipped as a god. IULIUS GRAECINUS, according to Seneca, was put to death for no other reason than that he was a better man than a tyrant liked to see alive”. KANUS IULIUS reproved the emperor to his face, and heard with calmness his own doom pronounced. During the ten days still left to him he went quietly on with his daily occupations ; he was engaged in a game of chess when the centurion summoned him. ‘After my death, he said to his opponent, ‘do not boast that you won the game.’ His philosopher accompanied him, and inquired how his thoughts were occupied. ‘I propose,’ said Kanus, ‘to observe whether at the last moment the soul is conscious of its departure. Afterwards, if I discover what the condition of departed souls is, I will come back and inform my friends*’’ In the reign of Claudius we find Stoics engaged in ἈΠ Ης actual conspiracy against the emperor. The name elder: of PAETUS CAECINA introduces us to a famous Stoic family, for his wife was ARRIA the elder. Pliny tells us, on the authority of her granddaughter Fannia, how when her husband and son both fell sick together, and the latter died, she carried out the whole funeral without her husband’s knowledge ; and each time that she entered his sick chamber, assumed a cheerful smile and assured him that the boy was much better. Whenever her grief became too strong, she would leave the room for a few minutes to weep, and return once more calm. When Scribonianus in Illyria rebelled against Claudius, Paetus took his side; upon his fall he was brought a prisoner to Rome. Arria was not allowed to accompany him, but she followed him in a fishing boat. She encouraged him to face death by piercing 7? “quem [Graecinum Iulium] C. Caesar occidit ob hoc unum, quod melior vir erat quam esse quemquam tyranno expedit’ Sen. Bev. ii 21, 5. 80. Dial. ix 14, 4-To. — her own breast with a dagger, declaring ‘it doesn’t hurt*!) and upon his death she determined not to survive him. Thrasea, her son-in-law, tried to dissuade her. ‘If I were condemned, would you, said he, ‘wish your daughter to die with me?’ ‘Yes, said Arria, ‘if she had lived with you as long and as happily as I with Paetus.’ Here we have a deliberate justification of the Hindu practice of the Sati. In the reign of Nero the Stoics are still more prominent, and almost always in opposition. SENECA, of Seneca. ὃ a8 : course, the emperor’s tutor and minister, is on the government side; and from his life we can draw the truest ~ picture of the imperial civil servant in high office. We shall certainly not expect to find that Seneca illustrated in his own life all the virtues that he preached ; on the other hand we shall. not readily believe that the ardent disciple of Attalus® and affectionate husband of Paulina was a man of dissolute life or of avaricious passions. Simple tastes, an endless capacity for hard work, and scrupulous honesty were the ordinary marks of the Roman official in those days, as they are of members of the Civil Service of India to-day*. Seneca, is often accused of having been too supple as a minister; but he was carrying out the principles of his sect better by taking an active part in politics than if he had, like many others, held sullenly aloof™. He did not indeed imitate Cato or Rutilius Rufus, who had carried firmness of principle to an extent that laid them open to the charge of obstinacy; but in submitting frankly to power greater than his own he still saw to it that his own influence should count towards the better side. For the story of his political career we cannot do better than to refer to the latest δὲ ‘casta suo gladium cum traderet Arria Paeto, | quem de visceribus traxerat ipsa suis, | ‘‘si qua fides, vulnus quod feci non dolet,”’ inquit, | ‘‘sed quod tu facies, hoc mihi, Paete, dolet”’’ Martial Zp. i14; ‘praeclarum illud eiusdem, ferrum stringere, perfo- dere pectus, extrahere pugionem, porrigere marito, addere vocem immortalem et paene divinam ‘‘ Paete, non dolet”’ Pliny Z¢. iii 16, 6. 82 See above, § 126. 83 “non derunt et frugalitatis exactae homines et laboriosae operae’ Sen. Diéa/. x 18, 4. For the British official the authority of the author of Zales from the Hills will suffice. - 84 See below, § 448, note 115. i ep eg — historian of his times®; of his work as a philosopher, to which he himself attributed the greater importance, a general account has been given above® and more particular discussions form the central theme of this book. From Seneca we pass naturally to some mention of
Persius ang the poets Persius and Lucan. A. PERSIUS FLACCUS pyeee: (34-62 A.D.) became at 16 years of age the pupil and companion of the Stoic philosopher Cornutus: he was also a relative of the Arriae already mentioned. He gives us a charming picture of his teacher’s ways of life, which were doubtless typical*’: and his summary view of the scope of philosophy: well indicates how its proportions had shrunk at this period. Dialectic is not mentioned, and physics has interest only in its bearing upon the position and duty of the individual. : “Go, study, hapless folk, and learn to know The end and object of our life—what are we; The purpose of our being here; the rank Assigned us at the start, and where and when The turn is smoothest round the perilous post ; The bounds of wealth ; life’s lawful aims; the use Of hoards of coin new-minted ; what the claims Of fatherland and kinsfolk near and dear; - The will of God concerning thee, and where Thou standest in the commonwealth of man*® His contemporary M. ANNAEUS LUCANUS (39-65 A.D.), a nephew of Seneca, plunged more deeply both into philosophy and into politics. In both he displayed ardour insufficiently tempered with discretion; he had a far keener sense of his personal grievances than became a Stoic,and was much more of a critic than of a reformer. Yet hardly any writer expresses more forcibly the characteristic doctrines of Stoicism, as they seized the imagination of young Romans of the upper classes. 85 Henderson’s Vero, pp. 31-38, 30-142, 257-288. 86 See above, 88 127-129. 87 See above, § 125. 88 Persius Saz. iii 66-72. The translations in this section are by Mr W. H. Porter. — Amongst such doctrines that of the conflagration was clearly prominent. ‘So when this frame of things has been dissolved, And the world’s many ages have received Their consummation in one final hour, Chaos recalled shall gain his utmost seat, The constellations in confusion dire Hurled each on each together clash; the stars Flaming shall fall into the deep; the earth No longer shall extend her barrier shores, And fling the waters from her; and the Moon Shall meet the Sun in fratricidal war®®.’ ‘One pyre awaits the Universe; in ruin ’Twill mix with bones of men the heavenly spheres.’ Lucan emphasizes the pantheistic interpretation of the divine nature ; ‘God is all eye can see or heart can feel.’ ‘The powers of heaven are round about us all; And though from out the temple come no voice, Nought can we do without the will of God%.’ To the idealized Cato he addresses the noblest praises ; ‘For sure a consecrated life is thine, The laws of heaven thy pattern, God thy guide®.’ ‘See the true Father of his country, worth The homage of thine altars, Rome; for they Who swear by him shall never be ashamed. If e’er the yoke is lifted from thy neck, Now or hereafter he shall be thy God®.’ The careers of Seneca and Musonius, and the early ets years of Lucan himself, indicate sufficiently that Civil service : Ay x and vole, there was no essential opposition between Stoic omans. ΩΝ πὰ τ ΒΕ principles and the Roman principate; in other \ words, that Stoics as such were not ‘republicans.’ Rather the contrary; for nearly all the Greek philosophers had been inclined | 89 Phars. i 72 to 80. 9 76. vii 814 and 815. 91 See above, § 242, note 9. 92 Phars. ix 573 and 574. 93 76. 556 and 557. 84 76. 601 to 604. The force of this tribute is impaired by the similar praise given to Pompey (Pars. vii 682-689) and to Brutus (16. 588 and 580). — to favour monarchy, and the Stoics had been conspicuous in the desire to abolish the distinctions of birth and class upon which the Roman aristocracy laid so much stress, and which the princi- pate was disposed to ignore. But in fact Stoicism was the common mould in which the educated youth of Rome were shaped at this period; it produced honest, diligent, and simple-minded men, exactly suited to be instruments of the great imperial bureaucracy. Large numbers entered the service of the state, and were heard of no more; such an one (except for Seneca’s incidental account of him) was C. LUCILIUS, Seneca’s correspondent. The great work of Roman government was carried on in silence, just as that of India in the present day. This silence was probably on the whole beneficial to society, though it was often felt as a constraint by theindividual. For this reason and many others there were at Rome (as everywhere and at all times) many able but disappointed men; they became the critics of the government, and from being critics they might at any time become conspirators; but at no period did they seriously aim at restoring the republican system. Their political creed was limited, and did not look beyond the interests of the class from which they sprang. They claimed for members of the senate at Rome their ancient personal privileges, and especially that of /zbertas, that is, freedom to criticize and even to insult the members of the government ; they sang the praises of Cato, celebrated the birthdays of Brutus and Cassius”, and practised a kind of ‘passive resistance’ based on Oriental methods, by quitting life without hesitation when they were baulked in their immediate wishes by the government. When the administration was carried on decently these men were ridiculous; when from time to time it became a scandal they were heroes. The early years of Nero’s reign show us plainly that! Republican the true spirit of Stoicism was far more developed prejudices. on the side of the government than on that of the aristocracy. Nothing distinguishes Seneca more honourably Ὁ than his humane attitude towards the slave population ; and he % «quale coronati Thrasea Helvidiusque bibebant | Brutorum et Cassi natalibus’ Juv. Sat. v 36 and 37. See also G. Boissier, Z’ Opposition sous les Césars. — was chief minister of the princeps when in the year A.D. 61 a ‘notable case®’ arose, in which the human rights of slaves were involved. The city prefect, Pedanius Secundus, was killed by one of his slaves. It was contended in the senate that by ancient custom the whole household, old and young, guilty and innocent, must be put to death alike; and this view prevailed and was carried into effect. Public opinion, according to Tacitus”, was unanimous against such severity; it looked, not unreasonably, to the emperor and his minister to prevent it’. They on the contrary left the decision to the free judgment of the senate. Where now were the men of philosophic principle, of world-wide sympathies, of outspoken utterance? The historian tells us that not one was found inthe senate. The honourable men who could defy an emperor’s death-sentence still lacked the courage to speak out against the prejudices of their own class; many indeed uttered exclamations, expressing pity for the women, the young, and the indubitably innocent, and even voted against the executions ; but even in so simple a matter there was not a man to follow the lead of Catiline in Cicero’s days, and take up as his own the cause of the oppressed. The leader of the merciless majority was C. Cassius Longinus, a celebrated jurist, and one who regularly celebrated the honours of Cassius the conspirator. But although the administration of which Nero was) Nero andthe ‘he head was largely manned by professed Stoics,) Stoics. and stood as a whole for the better sympathies of the Roman people, the course of court intrigue brought about a fierce conflict between the government and a growing force of public opinion of which the ‘old Roman’ group of Stoics were sometimes the spokesmen, and at other times the silent representatives. To Nero the consideration of his own safety was predominant over every consideration of justice to individuals and herein he stood condemned (and knew that it was so) by the judgment of all men of philosophic temper. The first of his 96 Henderson’s /Vero, pp. 90 sqq. 7 Annals xiv be 42, 2. %a The government had in fact appointed an officer for the prevention of cruelty to slaves : ‘de iniuriis dominorum in servos qui audiat positus est, qui et saevitiam et libidinem et in praebendis ad victum necessariis avaritiam compescat’ Sen. Bem. iii 22, 3. — victims, and perhaps the most deserving of our admiration, was RUBELLIUS PLAUTUS, accused by Tigellinus because he maintained the irritating cult of the ‘tyrannicides, and had joined the disloyal sect of the Stoics*. The charge of disloyalty against himself and his companions he disproved ; for, advised by his Stoic teachers Coeranus and Musonius, he declined to take part in a rising which might have been successful, and calmly awaited his fate (60 A.D.). In the conspiracy of Piso, which broke out a few years later, PLAUTUS LATERANUS is named by the historian as one of the few whose motives were honourable and whose conduct was consistently courageous”. The later years of Nero’s reign are illuminated in the pages of Tacitus by the firmness of men like THRASEA PAETUS, PACONIUS AGRIPPINUS, and BAREA SORANUS, and the heroic devotion of women like the younger ARRIA, Thrasea’s wife, and SERVILIA, the daughter of Soranus™. In the persecution of this group the modern historian finds extenuating circumstances, but at Rome itself it appeared as though the emperor were engaged in the attempt to extirpate virtue itself?” Upon the fall of Nero the ‘old Romans’ came for a eaten short time into power under the principate of Galba, PUSSIES and amongst others HELVIDIUS PRISCUS, Thrasea’s son-in-law, returned from exile. From the account of Tacitus he appears to have been a very sincere adherent of the Stoic school. ‘He was not like others who adopt the name of philosopher in order to cloak an idle disposition. He followed those teachers who maintain that only the honourable is good, and only the base is evil; power, nobility, and other things external to the soul being neither good nor evil. He designed so to fortify himself thereby against the blow of fortune that he could play his part in public affairs without flinching !™.’ His first act on returning to Rome was to commence a prosecution of the accuser of Thrasea. The senate was divided in opinion as to the wisdom of this step, and when Helvidius % Tac. Azz. xiv 57. *8 See Henderson’s Were, pp. 257-283. 100 Tac. Az. xvi 21-35. 101 * Nero virtutem ipsam exscindere concupivit ’ 26. 21. 105. ΥΥ͂ΣΟΣ 1G Ge — abandoned the suit some praised his charity, whilst others lamented his indecision’, He resumed his attempt, as we shall see, at a later time. Vespasian was undoubtedly tolerant in his views: his reign began with the restitution of honours to the deceased Galba, and the much-respected Musonius™ seized the opportunity to attack in the senate P. Egnatius Celer, whose treachery had brought about the fall of Soranus™, for false evidence. The trial was postponed, but resulted a little later in the condemnation of Celer™. Public opinion took the side of Musonius: but the accused found a champion in Demetrius the Cynic philosopher, and at least defended himself with the ability and courage of his sect. Thereupon Helvidius resumed his prosecution of the accuser of Thrasea; but the emperor, now anxious to let bygones be bygones, refused to approve”. This second failure appears to have embittered Helvidius: his opposition to Vespasian became open and insulting, and brought about his death”. The life of his wife FANNIA was worthy of the two Arriae, her grandmother and her mother. Twice she followed her husband into exile; a third time she brought this punishment upon herself, by encouraging his friend Senecio to publish his biography, supplying him with the materials, and openly justifying her action. In her private life she had singular charm and affability ; and her death appeared to Pliny to close an era of noble women™. His fall. It seems probable that the Stoic nobles found the low |
eu aa birth of Vespasian as intolerable as the tyranny of the Stoic Nero; at any rate they soon resumed their attitude’ eos of opposition to the government, and the punishment of Helvidius, if intended as a warning, proved rather a provocation. It appears that he and the ‘old Romans’ began a systematic propaganda in favour of what they called ‘democracy™, that is, the government of the Roman empire 103 Tac. Hist. iv 6. 104 See above, §§ 130, 131. 105 See above, § 444. 06 Tac. Hist. iv 40. 107 76. 43 and 44. 108 Dill, Roman Society, p. 152. . 9 Pliny Zp. vii 19, 7+ 10 +r ὄχλῳ προσέκειτο, βασιλείας Te ἀεὶ κατηγόρει, Kal δημοκρατίαν ἐπήνει Dion Cassius Ixvi 12. — by the senatorial class; and they probably involved many |professed philosophers in this impracticable and reactionary /movement. Vespasian resolved on expelling all the philosophers ‘from Rome. From this general sentence the best known of all, Musonius, was excepted™, and we must infer that he had shown the good sense to keep himself free from political entanglements. \In spite of this act of Vespasian, Stoicism continued to gain ground, and during the greater part of the period of the Flavian dynasty met with little interference. 448. But towards the end of the reign of Domitian a more | ἘΣ ἜΠΗ violent persecution broke out. ARULENUS RUSTICUS by Domitian. had been tribune of the plebs in 66 A.D., and had then proposed to use his veto in an attempt to save the life of - Thrasea Paetus™. In 69 A.D. he was praetor,and as such headed an embassy sent by the senate to the soldiers under Petilius Cerealis. On this occasion he was roughly handled and wounded, and barely escaped with his life’*. After many years of quiet, he was accused in 93 A.D., when Pliny was praetor, of having written and spoken in honour of Thrasea Paetus, Herennius Senecio, and Helvidius Priscus; he was condemned to death and his books were destroyed™. SENECIO was condemned at the same time for having written the biography of Helvidius Priscus, and for the further offence that since holding the quaestorship he had not become a candidate for any higher office’. About the same time were banished Artemidorus, the most single-minded and laborious of philosophers, whom Musonius had selected out of a crowd of competitors as the fittest to claim his daughter in marriage"; Junius Mauricus, brother of Arulenus Rusticus, who had joined Musonius in the attempt to secure the punishment of the delatores of Nero’s time™; Demetrius, and Epictetus™’; and further many distinguished ladies, including Arria and her daughter Fannia™. But from the time of the death of Domitian ΠῚ Dion Cassius lxvi 13. U2 See above, § 444. 18 Tac. Hist. iii 80. 14. Agr. 2; Suetonius, Dom. to. 15 Dion Ὁ. Ixvii 13, Tac. Agr. 45. 6 Pliny 422. iii 11, 7. 7 Το. 4715. ἵν 40. 8 A. Gellius VV. A. xv 11, 5 (for Epictetus). 9 Pliny .12. ili 11, 3; ‘tot nobilissimarum feminarum exilia et fugas’ Tac. Agr. 45. A. 26 ἴῃ A.D. 96 the imperial government became finally reconciled Ϊ . oie . . | with Stoicism, which was now the recognised creed of the great iene? ,majority of the educated classes at Rome, of all ages and ranks. As such it appears in the writings of JUVENAL, who not only introduces into serious literature the Stoic principle of ‘straight speaking,’ but actually expounds much of the ethical teaching of Stoicism with more directness and force than any professed adherent of the system. Stoicism, received into favour in the second century , A.D., won new opportunities and was exposed to Stoic reform pila, new dangers. Its greatest achievement lay in the development of Roman law. As we have just seen™, the ‘old ὦ Romans’ of Nero’s day, in spite of their profession of Stoicism, were unbending upholders of the old law, with all its harshness and narrowness; and we have to go back a hundred years to the great lawyers of the times of Sulla and Cicero™ to meet with men prepared to throw aside old traditions and build anew on the foundations of natural justice. But the larger view had not yet been lost sight of. It remained as the ideal of the more generous- minded members of the imperial civil service ; and in the times of the emperors Antoninus Pius (138-161 A.D.) and Marcus | Aurelius (161-180 A.D.) it became the starting-point for a new ‘development of Roman law, which is one of the great achievements of Roman history. The most eloquent of the historians of the origins of Christianity thus describes this movement. ‘Le stoicisme avait [déja] pénétré le droit romain de ses larges maximes, et en avait fait le droit naturel, le droit philosophique, tel que la raison peut le concevoir pour tous les hommes. Le droit strict cede a Véquité; la douceur l’emporte sur la sévérité; la justice parait inséparable de la bien- faisance. Les grands jurisconsultes d’Antonin continuérent la méme ceuvre. Le dernier [Volusius Moecianus] fut le maitre de Marc-Auréle en fait de jurisprudence, et, a vrai dire, l’ceuvre des deux saints empereurs ne saurait étre séparée. C’est d’eux que datent la plupart de ces lois humaines et sensées qui fléchirent la rigueur du droit ant que et firent, d’une législation primitivement étroite et implacable, un code susceptible d’étre adopté par tous les peuples civilisés!*2’ 120 See above, ὃ 443. 121 See above, §§ 428, 429. P 122 Renan, Marc-Auréle, pp. 22, 23; cf. Maine, Ancient Law, pp. 55, 56. +» In the legislation of Antoninus and Aurelius the humane and cosmopolitan principles of Stoic politics at last triumph over | Roman conservatism. The poor, the sick, the infant, and the | famine-stricken are protected. The slave is treated as a human being ; to kill him becomes a crime, to injure him a misdemean- our; his family and his property are protected by the tribunals. Slavery in fact is treated as a violation of the rights of nature; manumission is in every way encouraged. The time is within | sight when Ulpian will declare that ‘all men, according to natural right, are born free and equal.’ This legislation is not entirely the work of professed Stoics; it is nevertheless the offspring of Stoicism. There was in the second century, as there is still, a Repression SHAarp antagonism between the manners of culti- OS σϑεῖ vated society and the ardent profession of intellectual convictions. An anecdote related by Gellius well illustrates the social forces which were now constantly at work to check superfluous enthusiasm. ‘There was with us at table a young student of philosophy who called himself a Stoic, but chiefly distinguished himself by an unwelcome loquacity. He was always bringing up in season and out of season recondite philosophical doctrines, and he looked upon all his neighbours as boors because they were unacquainted with them. His whole talk was strown with mention of syllogisms, fallacies, and the like, such as the “ master-argument,” the “ quiescent,” and the “heap”; and he thought that he was the only man in the world who could solve them. Further he maintained that he had thoroughly studied the nature of the soul, the growth of virtue, the science of daily duties, and the cure of the weaknesses and diseases of the mind. -Finally he considered he had attained to that state of perfect happiness which could be clouded by no disappointment, shaken by no pains of death!4’ Such a man, we may think, might soon have become an apostle of sincere Stoicism, and might have left us a clear and systematic exposition of Stoic doctrine as refined by five centuries of experience. It was not tobe. The polished Herodes Atticus crushed him with a quotation from the discourses of Epictetus. Not many offended in the same way. Even Seneca 123 Renan, Marc-Auréle, p. 30. 124 Aulus Gellius 4. A. i 2, 3 to 5. ee had been severe on useless study in the regions of history and antiquity; the new philosophers despised the study even of philosophy. The Stoicism of the second century is therefore much anhoniic ka less sharply defined than that of earlier times. Its lishment of doctrines, acquired in childhood, are accepted with te eae ready acquiescence ; but they are not accompanied by any firm repudiation of the opposing views of other schools. Once more, as in the time of Augustus, the ‘ philosopher’ comes to the front; the particular colour of his philosophy seems of less importance”. It is philosophy in general which wins the patronage of the emperors. Nerva allowed the schools of the philosophers to be re-opened ; Trajan interested himself in them as providing a useful training for the young. Hadrian went further, and endowed the teachers of philosophy at Rome; Antoninus Pius did the same throughout the provinces. Marcus Aurelius established representatives of each of the philosophic schools at Athens; and amongst later emperors Septimius Severus, aided by his wife Julia Domna, was conspicuous in the same direction. The philosophers, who had firmly resisted persecution, gradually sacrificed their independence under the influence of imperial favour. They still recited the dogmas of their respective founders, but unconsciously they became the partisans of the established forms of government and religion. Yet so gentle was the decay of philosophy that it might be regarded as progress if its true position were not illuminated by the attitude of Marcus Aurelius towards the Christians. For Marcus Aurelius was universally accepted as the most admirable practical representative of philosophy in its full ripeness, and no word of criticism of his policy was uttered by any teacher of Stoicism. 125 «nam de illis nemo dubitabit, quin operose nihil agant, qui litterarum inutilium studiis detinentur, quae iam apud Romanos quoque magna manus est...ecce Romanos quoque invasit inane studium supervacua discendi,’ etc. Sen. Dza/. x 13, 1and 3. The condemnation extends to the whole study of history, /V. Q. iii Pr. 126 «In the purely moral sphere to which philosophy was now confined, the natural tendency of the different schools, not even excluding the Epicurean, was to assimila- tion and eclecticism’ Dill, Roman Society, p. 343.
The decay of precise philosophic thought was accom- The pagan Panied by a strong revival of pagan religious HEU NENc sentiment. The atmosphere in which Marcus Aurelius grew up, and by which his political actions were determined far more than by his philosophic profession, is thus sympathetically described by the latest editor of his Reflections. ‘In house and town, the ancestral Penates of the hearth and the Lares of the streets guarded the intercourse of life ; in the individual breast, a ministering Genius shaped his destinies and responded to each mood of melancholy or of mirth. Thus all life lay under the regimen of spiritual powers, to be propitiated or appeased by appointed observances and ritual and forms of prayer. To this punctilious and devout form of Paganism Marcus was inured from childhood ; at the vintage festival he took his part in chant and sacrifice ; at eight years old he was admitted to the Salian priesthood ; “he was observed to perform all his sacerdotal functions with a constancy and exactness unusual at that age; was soon a master of the sacred music ; and had all the forms and liturgies by heart.” Our earliest statue depicts him as a youth offering incense ; and in his triumphal bas-reliefs he stands before the altar, a robed and sacrificing priest. To him “prayer and sacrifice, and all observances by which we own the presence and nearness of the gods,” are “covenants and sacred ministries” admitting to “intimate communion with the divine !?”.”” The cult thus summarized is not that of the Greek mythology, much less that of the rationalized Stoic theology. It is the primitive ritualism of Italy, still dear to the hearts of the common people, and regaining its hold on the educated in proportion as they spared themselves the effort of individual criticism. It was by no mere accident that Marcus Aurelius State perse. Pe€came the persecutor of the Christians. He was Susie at heart no successor of the Zeno who held as essential the doctrine of a supreme deity, and absolutely rejected the use of temples and images. In the interval, official Stoicism \ had learnt first to tolerate superstition with a smile, next to become its advocate; now it was to become a persecutor in its name. Pontius Pilatus is said to have recognised the innocence 127 Rendall, AZ. Aurelius to himself, Introd. pp. cxxvii, CXXvill. of the founder of Christianity, and might have protected him had his instructions from Rome allowed him to stretch his authority so far; Gallio’* was uninterested in the preaching of Paul; but Aurelius was acquainted with the Christian profession and its adherents™, and opposed it as an obstinate resistance to authority’. The popular antipathy to the new religion, and the official distaste for all disturbing novelties, found in him a willing supporter. Thus began a new struggle between the - power of the sword and that of inward convicion. Because reason could not support the worship of the pagan deities, violence must do so™ It became a triumph of the civil authority and the popular will to extort a word of weakness by two years of persistent torture’. No endowed professor or enlightened magistrate raised his voice in protest; and in this feeble acquiescence Stoicism perished. For the consciences of the young revolted. Trained at Revolt of the ome and in school to believe in providence, in duty, young Stoics. and in patient endurance of evil, they instinctively recognised the Socratic force and example not in the magistrate seated in his curule chair, nor in the rustic priest occupied in his obsolete ritual, but in the teacher on the cross and the martyr on the rack™. In ever increasing numbers men, who had from their Stoic education imbibed the principles of the unity of the Deity and the freedom of the will, came over to the new society which professed the one without reservation, and dis- 128 The connexion (if any) of Gallio the proconsul of Achaia (Acts xviii 12) with the Junius Gallio who adopted Seneca’s elder brother is uncertain. 29 Renan, Marc-Auréle, p. 55, note 2. 130 M. Aurel. Zo himself xi 3. 131 Renan JZ.-A. p. 329. 132 ‘quia ratione congredi non queunt, violentia premunt; incognita causa tanquam nocentissimos damnant’ Lact. 7γ157. Epit. 47 (52), 4- 133 «vidi ego in Bithynia praesidem gaudio mirabiliter elatum tanquam barbarorum gentem aliquam ‘subegisset, quod unus qui per biennium magna virtute restiterat, postremo cedere visus esset’ Dzv. 7715. v ΤΙ, 15. 184 “nam cum videat vulgus dilacerari homines et invictam tenere patientiam, existimant nec perseverantiam morientium vanam esse nec ipsam patientiam sine deo cruciatus tantos posse superare...dicit Horatius: ‘“‘iustum ac tenacem...” quo nihil verius dici potest, si ad eos referatur qui nullos cruciatus nullam mortem recusant’ Ho 15. τ WO 1. — played the other without flinching. With them they brought in large measure their philosophic habits of thought, and (in far more particulars than is generally recognised) the definite tenets which the Porch had always inculcated. Stoicism began a new history, which is not yet ended, within the Christian church; and we must now attempt to give some account of ths after-growth of the philosophy.
Monday, October 3, 2022
Filosofia romana
Philosophy, on its first introduction into Rome in the wake of
Greek literature, art and science, encountered fierce opposition, but the personal influence of the younger Scipio and his * hmoeh of mends procured the nevrleaming a hearing; and the teachers, cuttun. notably Panaetius, had the tact to keep abstruse speculation out of sight and present their subject to their Roman pupils on its practical and literary side. Each of the three Schools most prominent at the time, the Stoic, the Epicurean and the New Academy, gained some adherents,
but the influence of the first was undoubtedly the greatest and the most
permanent It has been well said that the heroes of the early Republic
were unconscious Stoics, and no sooner was this system of moral plillosophy
made intelligible to cultivated Romans than it exercised an irresistible attraction. In a time when religious belief was decaying, the best intellects
welcomed in its place a doctrine which had so strong an affinity with the
national character: there was a sort of informal alliance between the public
policy and the philosophic convictions of such a man as Cato. But, though
phil(»ophy had its triumphs at Rome, it never quite shook off the national
prejudice. Having been committed to the Republican cause by Cato, the
Stoics were Rcnerally in opposition during the early Empire, and more than
once the government, as a precautionary measure, banished philosophers
from Rome. The educational value of philosophic study was, indeed,
recognised, and its wide influence is attested by much of the best literature. But zeal on the part of the pupils never supplied the lack of initiative ; they had no ambition to found new schools of thought, originality was confined either to the choice of a system (thus Varro selected the Old Academy out of aS8 possible systems), or to the arbitrary fitting together of various parts from different. ^sterns, according to the individual's own caprice. In confining their attention to popular philosophy and to practical questions, the Roman students conformed to, and by their adhesion strengthened, a tendency already powerful in the later Greek schools, where the con-
troversies of centuries had led to scepticism on the one hand and eclecticism on the other. The doctrine of Epicurus at the very outset excited general interest in Italy and was for a time exceedingly popular. Cicero tells us that crude translations of Epicurean text- LumtTui!'*"" books, written in a wretched style by Amafinius and others,
enjoyed a wide circulation {Acad, i 5, 6; l^sc Dhp. i 6, ii 7, iv 6 f; Ad
Fam. XV 19, 2). Curiosity fastened on a theory which offered explanations
of all the natural phenomena, especially those which have ever excited awe
and dread tn the popular mind. The poem of Lucretius, Ht £etuM
I^atura, which superseded these earlier efforts, was the fruit of a thorough
study and complete assimilation of the system, which he embraced with the
passionate enthusiasm of a religious convert. We are compensated. foLibe
almost total loss of the voluminous works of Epicurus himself by the match-
less exposition of his Roman pupil. The first two books lay down the
main principles of the system and trace the process by which the world was
formed, the next deals with the soul, in Book iv the difficult problem of
perception is grappled with, and the rest of the poem deals with celestial
phenomena, and generally with what is infrequent and obscure in the order
of Nature. One of the most interesting f)arts of the poem is the passive
(v 780 ff) in which is traced the gradual progress of mankind and the
growth of civil society. (Cp. §915 i supra.) Epicimis adopted fully the common principle of the Greek
physicists that every event has a natural cause (er nihiio nihil), which' it' is the business of the inquirer to discover. He fully recc^nised that the laws of nature are constant (i 592 — 598). From Democritus he 1
void!"""' "fJ^ over the atomic theory, which postulates two ultimate 1 eidstencffS: — matter, and void space, both constant and in-
destructible. Vord^exists fio less than matter : all nature consists of void
and matter, and nothing is ever added to the sum of things, nothing is
annihilated. But matter or body must be carefully distinguished from what
we call ' things'. Matter is the general term for the inRnity of minute
indivisible solids, which are"'t]ie indestructible constituents of 'things'.
'Things', in spite of their seeming solidity, are a^egates, containing void
space within them as well as solid matter. It is from the atoms of solid matter within them that sucli aggregates derive the name of bodies. Each atom is a little kernel, perfectly solid and therefore indestructible ; for, being wi^out void, it does aotadmitxhe
disintegrating i^ency of wet, cold and fire. Besides being solid, unchange-
able, everlasting, it has the property of rebounding after impact, now known
as 'elasticity^. Being extended, it can be conceived as having parts, but
the atom IS not a compound of these parts, which are inseparable from it.
Atoms differ in shape, size and weight, such difference being due to the
different disposition of their least parts. The number of atoms of each
shape is infinite; the numbenof the-diCTerent shapes, though large, is finite; 'SOtnetimcs, as in 'red', in 'fire' and in 'lightning', atoms are spherical. They are too small to be perceived by sense, we discern them by reason alone. The aggregates, or things which are made up of atoms, have many
secondary qualities, e.g. colour, taste, hardness or softness, heat or cold,
sound, and odour, but none of these belong to the atoms. Lucretius argues
that, if we postulate solid atoms, soft, porous bodies can be explained by
the presence in them of void, and hard bodies by the closer union of the
atoms, whereas, on the assumption that the first principles of things are not
solid atoms, but porous, and therefore soft, it would be impossible to
explain the hardness of bodies (i 565 — 576); further, that the constancy of
the phenomena of nature necessarily implies the unchangeableness of the atoms (i 584 — S9^)* Ih?_inQ5t marvellous property of the atom isjts mo-
bility. Matter does not cohere inseparably massed together ;
atoms are in ceasdesS_inQliQirt' After collision, they can
neyet stop,"lait rebound in an opposite direction, with the original velocity
unaltered. If atoms ever slopped, this would mean the destruction
matter. Even when combined, they are still in motion. If some n '
within very narrow limits, they must move to and fro oftener thai
which form more porous bodies; for the velocity of atoms i
stone or iron is as great as when they are streaming through the vS
Lucretius, as to modem science, heat is a mode of motion ; ind< conceived life itself as a mode of motion and the difference of atomic
structure in any two substances as sufficient to account for any difference in their qualities, even for that between the living and the lifeless. The inherent motion of the atom is in parallel lines downward ; at least, it would be so, but for a capricious tendency of individual atoms to swerve ever so slightly from the perpendicular. This dinamen must be assumed in order
to account for the fact that atoms moving with uniform velocity in one
direction ever came into collision at all (ii zi6 — 150). Given that collision, the gradual process by which a world like ours was evolved
can be traced step by step with inexorable consistency. Here,
as elsewhere, Lucretius refused to see any evidence of design ; he held
firmly that, Jf atoms exist, the world must have made itself. By a 'world'
hS-means a system containing an earthi a heaven and heavenly bodies, mth
the ether as a barrier to protect it against danger from withouL Relatiray,
the earth is a large part of this world and occupies a large part of the space within it ; for Epicurus trusted his senses so far as to believe that the apparent size of the heavenly bodies was approximately their real size
(v 564). From the infinite void, which contains an infinity of worlds, some
like our world, others unlike it, there is a constant stream of the fresh
atoms necessary to repair the waste which is constantly going on. Our;
world and all worlds had a beginning and will have an end, its structure isj already decaying and it will one day be once more reduced to its con-|
stituent and imperishable atoms, The sou] is mortal : it is as much corporeal as the body of the
animal, but its matter is incoinparabty finer, some of its constituents are not found in inanimate things, and it is the unique character of its composition which accounts for the motions of
sensation {sensi/eri mgtus). Soulj as sentient (am'ma), is diffused_all. QVer
the body, but its principal part (animus, mens) has its seat in the bre^t : the two, however, form a single nature. Of the four kinds of atoms composing the soul, the first to feel are those of the fourth nameless substance; their motions are the sensations, which are transmitted to the atoms of heat, then to those of wind, then to those of air, and finally to those of the whole body. The beating of the heart in fear or joy proves that, like thought and will, the passions have their seat in the animus, where soul-atoms are condensed and give rise to a greater variety of complex motions. The
PencDtioD processes of sensation and intellect are alike explained on
the assumption of contact between the material soul and the
material object In some of the senses (sight, hearing and smell), and in
^ination, memory and thought, contact is not directly with the external
'tself, but with a film or husk given off by the object, which travels
khe intervening space and is lodged in the sensenji^jan or the mind,
^sary to assume that all bodies are constantly giving otT such iilms
_ ntions {simulacra, ti&oXa) of infinitesimal depth or thickness, but
preserving more or less faithfully the superiicial shape of the bodies which
discbarge them. The constant emission of particles by radium may serve
I to illustrate this hypothesis. It is in keeping with the rest of the system
\ that Epicurus derived all knowledge from the senses ; no one sense could
correct another, for their objects are different ; nor could reason correct
impressions of sense, for reason is ultimately derived from sense. . This
implicit trust in sense made Epicurus sceptical of the mathematical sciences,
which he supposed to contradict it; and the current views on astronomy he
rejected, whenever they conflicted with the evidence of the senses. He
demanded clear and explicit testimony for every inference; and, if this
could not be given, his conception of physical research was limited to the
suggestion of means by which, without contradicting known facts, the
phenomena in question might have come about. He preferred, where
possible, several explanations, and left us to take our choice. In ethics,
h(*was a hedonist : the pleasure of the agent is the only standard of con-
g , ducL^Cic De Finibus, i and ii). But pleasure is an ambiguous term, and it is not the excitement of the moment, but the
calm feeling of satisfaction, which succeeds the removal of discomfort,
which he set up as the end. Human misery springs largely from unsatisfied
wants: natural desires are easily satisfied, some desires are unnecessary and ought not to be gratified. This is still more true of Che whole class of
artificial or conventional desires, which are stimulated by idle fancy and the
opinion of others, the gratification bringing the agent no direct pleasure at
all. Ambition and the love of fame are illustrations. Justice is entirely
conventional, but the agent finds his advantage in fulfilling contracts and
'obeying authority, for 'honesty is the best policy'. Virtue should be
pursued, not as an end in itself, but as a means (indeed, as society is
constituted, a necessary and indispensable means) to happiness, which, as we have seen, means tranquil pleasure, /The existence of gods
* ' *' is guaranteed by our ideas and imaginations of them, which
must have an external cause. They are blessed and immortal beings,
inhabiting the inttrmundia, or interspaces between world and world, and
taking no part in the government of the world, a task which would effectu-
ally interfere with their happiness. On friendship Epicurus
'"' laid especial stress : it guaranteed the highest and purest
pleasure. The members of his school were to be a band of brothers and at the cost of some inconsistency, he maintained that on behalf of a friend
the wise man would even dare to die.
iosi> The interest of Cicero in philosophic studies was life-long and
sincere. He had good opportunities for becoming acquainted
with all the schools and had heard most of the leading men. ' ^ His reading was wide and directed by the ambition of adding a ntm
department to Roman literature. In the proems or introductions toMiis
dialogues, he combats the current opinion that the public were not ii^rested in philosophy and that it could not be effectively expounded in Latin. His own contributions were, as he tells Atticus (Ad Alt. xii 51), translations:
'droypa^ sunt,...uerba tantum adfero, quibusabundo'. He also supplied
the setting and the numerous illustrations from Roman life and history. He had no original views to publish, he merely expounded those of others,
taking them from some received Greek authority, Panaetius in De Officiis,
and possibly H&ato in the De Finibus. But, for exposition, he had a
rare talent and uncommon advant^es ; and, for all the haste with which he
wrote, he was fired with enthusiasm for his subject and vrith the desire to
produce a really good book upon it. (Cp. § 972 supra.") As Cicero professedhimself an adherent of the New Academy, it
is necessary to explain the meaning of the term before we proceed to con-
sider his exact relation to contemporary thought Plato's school, after the
death of its founder, had passed through many vicissitudes. /FgL^^tirne
the teaching was rjngtnntin nnd mniply p^hiral the peculiM: Platonic
metaphysics being either greatly modified or quietly" propped. In this
phase Tl~ft known as Hm Old Academy. TTTis dogmatic teaching was
abandoned by Arc£silas (died 140 b.c), under whose headship the school
became the home of scepticism, by which is meant free inquiry, unbiassed
by any positive conviction. As much could be advanced for, as against,
any opinion under discussion, and the wise man, renouncing absolute
knowledge as unattainable, held his judgement in abeyance
(iirox^). This sceptical phase is known generally as the New AMdrmy",
Academy. Sometimes, however, Arcesilas and his immediate
successors are called the Middle Academy, and the New Academy proper is
made to begin a century later with CarnSides (214 — 129), the most gifted
of all the successors of Plato. Arcesilas and Carneades both contended that, in their scepticism, they were the legitimate heirs of the Socratic and
Platonic traditio'nT^^ut it was one thing to maintain with Arcesilas the
abstract thesis that knowledge is unattainable : it was another and harder
task to prove by argument that it had not been attained. Cameadeji
essayed this task. He undertook to overthrow the existing dogmatic
systems by a refutation of their dogmas in detail, and the negative dialectic
with which he attacked them made him the terror of all his contemporaries,
jMrticularly the Stoics. At the same time, he developed a doctrine of ,
probability which, so far as action was concerned, served as a substitute for
the certainty which he regarded as beyond our reacK In the long run,
however, simple agnosticism failed to satisfy the tendency of the time, which
became ever more distinctively eclectic and sought to discover in the
different schools a common basis for practical morality. Some concessions
to dogmatism were made by Philo of Larissa (c. 88) : things, he said, were
in their own nature knowable, but not by the standard of knowledge which
th« Stoics proposed. His disciple, Antiochus of Ascalon (^. 78), weary of
a |ppeless straggle, at length recanted his agnostic errors and declared
knowle^e to be possible. In thus violently breaking with the sceptical
tradition of the past two centuries, he professed to revive the Old Academy,
but the staple element of his eclectic doctrine was distinctively Stoic,
although, in defiance of plain historical fact, he accused the Stoics of having
borrowed it without acknowledgement from the Academy. In Cicero's case there is a wide gulf between speculative inquiries in general and (heir particular application to morals. On
Phiiouphic tjjg theoretical issue, he remained loyal to the scepticism, or
poillieo of , . . ' „ ,4-, .. J, Cicera. rather agnosticism, of Cameades. He was equally opposed to the compromise of Philo and the downright surrender of
Antiochus. He valued highly the privilege of criticising all opinions without being committed unreservedly to the defence of any, a privilege which
a barrister above alt men would appreciate. Nothing can be known, but
one opinion may be maintained as more probable than another. When,
however, we come to questions of law and morality, the case is different.
The use which Cicero here makes of his freedom to hold whatever opinion
seems probable, is a singular one. He wholly dissociates himself from the
negative views of Cameades. Nothing had done so much to prejudice the
average Roman against philosophy at the very outset as the versatility with
which Cameades on two successive days advocated arguments, first for, and
then against, the obligations of justice. With such an attitude Cicero had no sympathy, any more than with the utilitarian ethics of Epicurus. A
violent reaction against both led him at first to accept the eclecticism of
Antiochus, but gradually he approximated more closely to the Stoics, whose
rigid consistency and moral idealism had an attraction for him, as for other
Romans, in spite of [he hard criticism which he passed upon them-
Hence, in reviewing his opinions, we have to distinguish the pupil of
Cameades, in the Academica, De Natura Deorum, De Diuinatiom and De
Fate, from the pupil of Antiochus, in De Legibus and De Finibus, and from
the defender of Stoic ethics in the Tusailam and t>e Offidis. We can
never be sure, however, whether any opinion advanced in Cicero's works is
really his own, and he protests emphatically that he is not bound by
previous utterances and that it is a mistake to fasten upon himself the
inconsistencies of his different writings {Tusc. v 33 and 82 f)'. ' How diflicult ii is, in the absence of a irualworthy clue, (o infer from internal
evidence what authority he \% al the time following may be seen from one instance. In
Ihe Tuieulan Diipulatiom the preference is given lo the Stoic conception of emotion, as
somelbing, in its own nature, vicious, and therefore 10 be eradicated. The more
ro53— loss] In the current view, there were two great problems of philosophy,
one theoretical, the criterion of truth, the other practical, the
end of action. With the first of these Cicero deals in the T'le ciiurioo
Acadtmica. The question discussed is whether knowledge is Aca^timica.
possible, and the single book of the earlier edition now extant
gives the arguments of the dogmatist for, and of the agnostic (in the person of Cicero) against, this possibility. The former points to the body of received
truth possessed by the arts and sciences and insists on the suicidal inconsistency of the Sceptic in maintaining, whether dogmatically or otherwise,
that knowledge is impossible. Moreover, such a view paralyses action,
brings man to the level of a machine, and renders definition impossible.
But the stress of the Carneadean onslaught had reduced the dogmatists to
the defensive, and much space is devoted to an examination of those facts of experience (hallucinations, dreams, delusions of the insane) from which
the inference was apparently irresistible that there was no criterion for
discriminating the true from the false. On this issue, the reply of the
agnostic is overwhelming. The position of the Epicurean, who placed
implicit faith in the senses, is intelligible, that of the Sceptic, who distrusted
them all, is likewise intelligible, but a dogmatist has to base knowledge on
the senses, while at the same time admitting that they are sometimes
deceived. That this is impossible is shown in detail. For action, again,
Cicero insists that probability is just as good a guide as knowledge.
Lastly, in a review of the entire history of philosophy, he dwells with
evident delight upon the inconsistent and sometimes absurd opinions on
every conceivable subject advanced by different Schools. What, then,
becomes of that body of received truth which is the common possession of
the sciences ? The exact impression which the treatise De Natura Deorum
was intended to leave on the reader, is not quite clear. The honours of
debate rest with the negative critic, although the author professes his own
sympathy with the Stoic supporter of orthodoxy. The theological views of
the two great contemporary Schools, the Stoic and the Epicurean, are alone
seriously expounded, and are in turn subjected to merciless criticism at the
hands of the New Academy, represented by Cotta. \n De Diuinatione
and De Fato (the latter a fragment) the treatment is very similar. A Stoic
doctrine, in the one case divination, in the other fate, is first expounded
and then riddled with all the skill and ingenuity of that negative criticism
in which Carneades excelled. The other chief problem of philosophy was a practical one : what
is the chief good ? This forms the subject of De Finibus. The Epicurean doctrine that pleasure is the end of action is ^"/'.viw"?''" ' expounded in Book i and refuted from Stoic sources in Book II. Stoicism finds a champion and exponent in the person of Cato mtxletate doclrlne of Ihe Academy, which permitted emotion to be indulged wilhin
bounds, is rejecied. Vet, in spiie of ihis Stoic linge, some scholars contend that this
treatise is modelled upon a work by the Academic Philo. in Book 111. The reply of Cicerd in Book iv is on the lines of Antiochus,
embodying his unhistorical assumption that there was no real difTerence on
ethics between the Stoics and the Old Academy, and that Zeno stole the
doctrines of his predecessors and invented a ctabbed terminology to
conceal the theft. The views of Antiochus on the whole question of the
chief good are presented as a positive doctrine in Book v. He did not
hold with the Stoics that virtue alone is self-sufficient for happiness; the
complex nature of man requires that he should be adequately furnished
with corporeal and external, as well as with mental, goods. Nevertheless,
virtue is the supreme, though not the only, good. In the earlier unfinished
work, De Legiius, law is treated from the same Antiochean standpoint but
with closer approximation to Stoicism, and the New Academy is quietly
snubbed (i 39). Cicero is sometimes said to have been the first to state
explicitly that all men have innate moral ideas (notiones innatae, natura
nobis insltae), and that the belief in the existence and immortality of God is
found in mankind everywhere (eonsensus gentium). But, on closer examina-
tion, we discover that Cicero's innate ideas are merely his somewhat
rhetorical way of presenting the Stoic conception of hvouii or rpoK^^tvi,
and, as these are similarly developed in normal man everywhere, the Stoics
often employed the argument from consensus gentium. Cicero's accuracy has often been impugned. But,'setting aside
the carelessness ineWtable in hasty writing {e.g. Acad. Post. ecuracy. . ^^^^ ^^^ gravei charge has not been substantiated. He is
our earliest authority for the later Greek systems; at the time he wrote, the Stoa and the Academy had passed through many phases of doctrine, and,
except in a few cases where he cites his authority, it is not easy to determine which phase or which philosopher he is reporting. As a mere
question of probability, the chances are far greater that his statements are
accurate than that we have the means of correcting them- His very
dependence upon his sources (of which the translation of part of Plato's
Timaeus for the purpose of insertion in some work contemplated, but never
written, is a proof), makes his philosophical writings a treasure-house of r.luable fragments and testimonia.
1057. In the history of Stoicism it is usual to distinguish three periods.
In the first, from Zeno (c. 350 — 264) to the death of
of'stoic'i^' Chrysippus {e. 208-4), 'he theory was elaborated. The
next two centuries form a period of transition, during which
the older doctrines were modified, simplified and occasionally relaxed in an eclectic spirit : it was in this modified form that they began to be taught at
Rome. In the last period, under the Empire, the practical Roman intellect
made its influence felt by a reaction against scientific theory altogether.
1058. Zeno (ob. 364), the founder of .the school, adopted the famous
threefold division of philosophy into (i) Iq^ic, (2) physics,
stai!^iiii. including psychology and theology, and (3) ethics. Logic is a mere propaedeutic of philosophy, its most important function being to determine what is the standard of truth. The Stoics adopted
an empirical theory of knowledge ; not, however, without concessions to
rationalism. At lirst, we are told, they were content with right reason as
the standard, but, as their doctrine became definitely more materialistic,
they looked for their criterion in sensation, empirical notions or pre-
conceptions, as well as in vpokij^w {noiiorus, ttotitiae). The presentations
or impressions (uim, iJMvTiuriiu), which the senses convey to the mind, are often erroneous A certain peculiar definite- ^f'^th'*''"'
ness, a degree of force, in impressions is the ultimate test of
their truth, because it satisfies us, immediately and irresistibly, that such an impression must proceed from a real object and agree with it and could
not have been produced by an unreal object. When this is the case, the
mind, itself active, by giving assent (aiisensio, miyKaToBtuii) to the im-
pression, grasps and apprehends a real object. Like all the later Schools,
the Stoics were materialists. Nothing exists but body,
for body alone is capable of acting and being acted upon.
At the same time, any mechanical explanation of the universe, such as
that of £[ifi:{iKis/ is insufficient, and must give place lo a teleolt^'cal
explanation. Everywhere we see the adaptation of means lo ends : as
in human actions, so in nature, every event fulfils a purpose. If this
teleolt^y is combined with dynamic materialism^ the result is monism or
pantheism. What ultimately exists is at once spirit and matter, or, in other
words, spirit is itself one, the purest, form of matter, viz. ether. We must
conceive it as fiery breath and carefully distinguish it, as the element of warmth, by which all life is sustained, from the destroying fire which we know upon earth. This divine primitive substance may either remain what
it is in its purity, or it may be transformed by perpetual succession into its
various modifications, the four elements, out of which all particular things,
all bodies, animate or inanimate, are formed. All of them are permeated
by the divine ether or spirit in varying degrees of tension. This identical
essence, manifested in diverse forms in everything that exists, makes the
universe one. Moreover, its unity is not that of casual a^egation : it
forms an organic whole, to which all the parts are so related that they are
in mutual sympathy; and, whatever directly affects one member, affects
them all. For the world is a living being, an animal, 'whose
body Nature is, and God the soul". It is both sentient and
intelligent. By intelligence it conthils and directs all that happens ;
whether it be called 'Reason, Providence, Nature, or Fate, makes no
difference. God is meant by all these terms, and God is the living
universe. The creation, development, and ultimate destruction of this
universe, are all phases in the life of this eternal Being. By the unceasing
law of fate a time will come when the world and all that it contains will be
merged in the primeval fire, only to be created anew, when it will run
identically the same course as before. Pope's Essay en Man, i 968. The parallel between the individual and the universe, the
The tout microcosm and the macrocosm, is best seen in psychology. As God is, in essence, fiery breath, the soul of the universe,
so the soul which holds tc^ether and moves the human body is a fiery
breath or sentient exhalation, fed by exhalations from the blood. Here
is a striking contrast with the Epicurean psychology. In both systems
the soul is corporeal, but, in that of Epicurus, life, sensation and reason
are produced from lifeless atoms, themselves devoid of sensation and
reason. According to the Stoics, the soul grows to the perfection of reason
with the growth of the body. Its essence is one, its varying functions
being conditioned by the varying degrees of tension in its substance.
There can be no distinct parts of the soul, as maintained by Plato and
Aristotle ; and, when the Stoics speak of eight parts, they are careful to
explain them as currents or channels, permeating the whole body and
connecting the ruling principle {Y/t/iovixuv) in the heart with the extremities.
The soul is not immortal, but after separation from the body the souls of
the wise endure for a time, viz., until the general conflagration at the end
of the present cycle of existence.
On this groundwork of physics the Stoics based their ethical doctrine. Good, the end of life, is defined as agreement
with nature — whether the individual nature of man or, as Cleanthes maintained, the nature of the universe, had been left undefined by Zeno. Chrysippus held that the term 'nature' embraced both. This harmony with nature consists in virtue. Virtue is the one unconditional good, good at all times and under all circumstances. Similarly, vicis is absolutely and at all times evil. All intermediate things are morally indifferent {intiifermiia, dSuii^opa), but have d^rees of worth and worth- lessness, positive and negative value {aestimatio, inaesHmalio), according as they are in conformity with, or contrary to, nature. Such value as belongs to things indifferent, is not a permanent attribute, but is contingent upon circumstances: so that what at one time accords with nature, may at another time conflict with it The emotions are not produced by any principle in the soul distinct from reason ; for the unity of the soul would be sacrificed by the recognition of any such principle. They can only be defined as morbid states of the reason itself, due to excessive Impulse and ultimately to an erroneous judgement The soul which forms a iaise estimate of the value of things, is hurried by a violent and irregular movement towards fancied goods in pleasure and desire and away from fancied evils in grief and fear, these being the four leading species of emotion. The contrast here with the teaching of Plato and Aristotle is obvious. So long as parts or faculties of the soul, essentially distinct, were recognised, it was the function of the reason to regulate and control the impulses of the lower animal nature, fiut the Stoics deduce from the unity of the soul the unity of its activity, whether in a healthy or a morbid state. Hence they demanded no mere regulation of the passions, but their entire suppression and eradication. The absence of reason not only renders virtue impossible in the child or in the brute ; it makes emotion and vice equally impossible. The truly 'wise' man performs all his actions in accordance with reason and virtue, being preserved by his wisdom from intellectual error, no less than from moral failings. Mankind are sharply divided into the two classes of the 'wise' and the 'foolish'; and, as virtue and vice admit of no degrees, every action of the former is a right action (rettum, icoropSui/ui), of the latter is wrong {pueatutn, dfiapTTj/ta). Here Stoicism approaches Christian ethics : the passionless sage, like the Christian saint, is set over against a world lying in wickedness, The change from the state of folly to the state of wisdom was at first regarded as an instantaneous conversion, and the question- of final perseverance, or the possibility of a lapse from wisdom, had as much interest for the older Stoics as for Christian theologians. In the above meagre outline the moral idealism of the earlier Stoics is as conspicuous as the optimism of their physics. Otj^er creeds and systems point 10 a brighter future, whether on earth itself or in a life beyond: Stoicism takes the world as it is, and resolutely finds it here and now perfect. It can hardly be said to have flourished in Greece. Men were repelled by its indifference to art and culture, its swictamin pedantic formalism, and uncouth terminology. Two causes thcHcsnd profoundly altered its character and prospects; firstly, the P^^od. criticism of Carneades, who fastened upon the many inconsistencies of the Stoics and compelled the more intelligent among them to reconsider their position ; secondly, the necessity of modifying what was originally a speculative doctrine, to meet the needs of the Romans. The two men most instrumental in introducing philosophy to Rome were also the most considerable figures in the middle period of Stoicism and handled the traditional doctrine with great freedom. PanaeCius (180 — in), the friend of Scipio and Laelius, came as the missionary of Hellenic culture, commending to his Roman pupils the works of Plato, whom he reverenced and admired, as readily as those of his Stoic predecessors. He himself diverged from orthodoxy on several points. He denied the doctrine of a general conflagration and, in consequence, the limited immortality which early Stoics had held out as the privilege of the souls of 'wise' men. He rejected the old Stoic doctrine of divination. In these de- viations it is easy to trace the influence of Carneades. In ethics, he adopted a terminology less calculated to offend common sense and common prejudices. He divided virtues into two classes, theoretical and practical. Without altogether abandoning the aspiration after perfect wisdom and virtue, he recognised that his business was with those who had set out on the road to virtue, and were a long way removed from the ideal 'sage.' It was for these he wrote his treatise ir«pi roij mi^ ncotTM, of which we have a paraphrase in the first two books of Cicero's De Officiis, dealing successively with the (MAdK or honestum, and the u^fXifioi' or ulile. Poseiddniiis of Apimfa (c. 130 — 46) was the pupil of Panaetius, and the last great Stoic who took an interest in theoretical philosophy! ^nd busied himself with the positive sciences. It is probable that his work n-fpi 0(uv has been used by Cicero in Book it of the De Natura Deorvm. As regards divination and the general conflagration, he fell back upon the orthodox Stoic view. In psychology, he abandoned the strict unity of the soul, finding it impossible to explain the emotions as morbid conditions of the reason, and'with Plato and Aristotle assumed an irrational part of the soul (ira^riKdi') to account for them. He also maintained the immortality, and, very probably, the preezistence, of the rational soul. Many tendencies in the later Stoics, such as Seneca and Marcus Aurelius, are explained by his influence. The Romans in general cared little for the ground-work of theory. Attitude t* ''"' vicx^ profoundly interested in all which concerned religion, the popular The Stoics from the first, while maintaining that the universe "ligion. j^ God, had taken the popular theology under their patronage. Rationalising and allegorising the myths, they could interpret the many divinities of the poets as all manifestations of the one supreme Being. In this defence of the truth in polytheism, etymology played a large part. Nor, again, if all events happen by divine ordinance, is it at all unreasonable to suppose that what is fore-ordained should be disclosed by God to His rational creatures through signs and portents for their warning and instruction. Upon this principle, and upon the interdependence and close sympathy existing between all parts of the one universe, was based the philosophic defence of augury, oracles and divination. This twofold attitude of the system, at once tolerant and critical, towards the popular beliefs and cults attracted the Roman statesmen who, anxious, on polirical grounds, to uphold the national faith, gladly accepted the assurance of the philosophers that it was an imperfect adumbration of ultimate truth. In the Second Book De Natura Deorvm, we find Cicero's Stoic DcMumii advancing the most dissimilar arguments to prove the existence of the gods. Some of them are wholly inconclusive, such as the universal belief of mankind : for this wide-spread belief in anthropomorphic beings, resting partly on legends of their intervention in human affairs, certainly could not establish what the Stoics wished to prove, viz., that the universe itself is living, sentient, intelligent and perfect. Again, to argue from divination, auguries and oracles is. to ai^ue in a circle, for the divine existence would be assumed as the main argument in support of divination. Popular superstition might be satisfied with such grounds of belief, but the philosophical arguments, cited from Zeno and Chrysippus, are of a very different order. They start with the assumption that the universe is perfect What has reason is better than what has not reason : therefore the universe, as the best of things, must possess reason. ' The universe as a whole must be more perfect than its parts, it must be sentient, because it has sentient parts ; and intelligent, because one part, man, is intelligent. The inference is from the effect to the cause. We assume that there are everywhere the marLs of adaptation and design, such as no human reason, or human power, could produce : the effects, and in particular the phenomena of the heavenly bodies, point to a cause, and this must be an intelligence superior to that of man. The scale of existence rises by gradual ascent from vegetable to animal, from animal to human existence ; and, if the universe is perfect, this scale must be completed in a Being who is perpetually virtuous and wise, in whom the striving after perfection common to all finite natures finds its fulfilment. These a^uments establish the divinity of the whole universe, conceived, as in Plato's Timaeus, as spherical. But its activity is not limited to the eternal revolution of the heavenly sphere. It is displayed in the creation and government of the particular beings over whom it exerts its providence. The highest of such individual existences are the spirits of the stars, inhabiting the purest element, ether. From the point of vantage obtained by these results the gods of mythology admit of easy explanation. They are personifications either of the forces of nature, like Jupiter and Neptune ; or of benefits universally enjoyed, lite Ceres and Liber ; of virtues and passions, hke Concord, Victory, Ops and Venus ; or even of departed
human benefactors, like Hercules, Aesculapius and Quirinus. Here, it is easy to recognise two distinct lines of argument. The cosmological proof or argument from design is used explicitly, the ontological used implicitly, when it is assumed that the universe is perfect and thtrefore corresponds in actuality to our conception of what is perfect. The opposition of the Stoics to the Epicureans was bitter and uncompromising, and many parts of the system are best explained by contrast with Epicurean tenets. This is the case with the doctrine of providence. The working of intelligence, the adaptation of means to ends, which the Stoics saw every- where, was fiercely denied by Epicurus. The God of the Stoics foreknows and ordains all events, even to the minutest details ; the Epicureans, and agnostics like Carneades, joined issue with them, pointing to the calamities which befall the innocent and the virtuous and to notorious examples of prosperous villainy. It was easy to retort that external circumstances are not the rewards of virtue or of vice. Still, a difficulty remained in the familiar fact of ' conquered good and conquering ill ', which is but a part , of the tai^er problem, the existence of moral evil in a perfect universe. This problem the Stoics were bound to face, and they offered the best solution they could. Either, it may be said, God is the author of all things except wickedness ; or, the very nature of good presupposes its contrary, evil ; or, there may be a point of view from which what we call evil is not evil. The same fundamental difference of view appears, when the two Schools, at the outset of their ethical inquiries, take up the purely psychological question: — what are the objects of natural and instinctive desire? It may seem absurd to assume that any special importance for ethics can attach to observations of the unreasoning actions of children and the lower animals. However, both Schools joined in making the assumption and only differed as to the fnterpretation of the facts. Epicurus interpreted them as showing that every movement and action was directed to the attainment of pleasure. The Stoics asserted, on the contrary, that, not pleasure nor freedom from pain, but self-preservation, was the end instinctively sought. The exposition of Stoic ethics in the &t FinibM •pjjjj.j gj^jj j^^ Finibus starts from this point In man, as in every other animal, from the moment of birth natural impulse {appefiius, ipi^n) prompts to self-preservation, and to the mun- tenance of the physical frame in its original integrity. Thus, self-love is anterior in our experience to pleasure or pain and is presupposed in all pursuit of particular pleasures or avoidance of particular pains. The objects of these early impulses, the so-called prima naturae (or s-piuni koto ^vviv), are partly corporeal, health and bodily soundness, partly mental, the knowledge which we acquire, either directly through the senses or in- directly through the arts and sciences : they do not include naiune. pleasure. The phrase prima naturae was adopted by the Stoics from the Old Academy, and the relation to virtue of these primary natural advantages caused no little trouble, exposing them to damaging criticism. According to the strict theory of the Older School, these objects must belong to the class of things intermediate, which in themselves are neither good nor evil ; no added value can make them good ; any such addition is infinitesimal in comparison with the absolute value which attaches to virtue. And yet, under the pressure of con- troversy, the Stoics of the middle period endeavoured to bring them into some sort of connexion with the end. Cicero's Stoic speaks of them, like all things intermediate, as the field for the exercise of wisdom. Though not in themselves good, they are secondary results procured by what is moral, honeslum, ro koXov (De Fin. iii 31, 39. 49). Thus, all or most of the things commonly judged to be good (though the older Stoics had refused to call them so) — such as health, strength, wealth, fame — are brought within the sphere of the wise man's choice, and yet his real good still lies solely in the wisdom of the''choice, and not in the thing chosen. This is illustrated by a simile : — an archer aims at a bull's eye, but his end is not the mark itself, but the manifestation of his skill in hitting it (16. iii 2i). The same tendency is shown in the classification of actions. Of intermediate things, those which are natural are to be preferred (praepotita, Trporrfi^iva); their opposites, which are contrary to nature, are to be rejected {reiecta, a.irtnrpoijyfi.a'a.). Every action connected with the former is an appropriate action {officium, KoBi^Kov), which is dehned as 'any action, the performance of which admitsjof reasonable justilication '. Reason requires us to perform such actions. The wise man and the fool alike choose what is natural, and reject what is contrary to nature, so that here they are on common ground. Both may perform the same external act, e^. of faithfully returning a deposit ; it is the motive which underlies the performance which makes the difference. The action is not virtuous unless it be done with the right intention, which the possession of wisdom can alone ensure. Virtuous action is appropriate action carried to perfection, and this implies the imperfect performance (in^atum officiutn or simply efficium, fMaov KaBiJKOv). It was inevitable that, as the perfect sage receded more and more into the region of the ideal, moralists should take more and more account of these appropriate actions ; and this offiaum of the Stoics, and not the KaropSioiJM, forms (he startii^-point for the modern conception of duty. The view thus taken of appropriate action or inchoate duty admits of a very special application to the case of suicide, which was regarded as permissible, ^^^^ for the wise and unwise alike, under stress of special external circumstances. We must remember that the Stoics held the good to be independent of time; the temporal , prolongation added no whit to happiness. Its characteristic is seasonableness («wcoipia). We must further remember that lijjej and death belong to the class of things intermediate which .gj^s'ubmitted to the wise man's choice, and which determine all his plans. If anyone, on reviewing his external circumstances, finds that those in accord with nature preponderate, it is appropriate for him to remain in Ufe ; if the balance inclines the other way, or seems likely to do so, it is appropriate to quit life (migrare de uila, tvXnym iiaytoYn)- The door is open ; nothing compels him to stay. The principle here laid down (th. 60, 6t) covers the case of Cato himself, and of the host of Stoics who, particularly in the reign of Nero, followed his example. It was on the social side of ethics that the Stoic theory presented the greatest contrast with that of Epicurus. The latter had _ , . ,, , ■ , ■ , r r 1 • , f Socl«l ethlci. no place in his scheme for a mans duties to the State, or even 10 his neighbours, unless they were his friends. The Epicurean sage would not marry, would not engage in politics, would not, in fact, assume any of the responsibilities of social life, from which, nevertheless, he strove to derive as much advantage for himself and his friends as possible. His motto was Aa'fl< ^luo-as. Here, however, where their opponents were weakest, the Stoics made their most original contributions to practical morality. They conceived the whole universe as a common- wealth embracing gods and men, under divine government and with a common law in virtue of the reason which man shares with God (Dt Finibus, iii 64; De Ltgibus, i 33). They taught that the general interest must be preferred to our own. They required men to maintain the obligations of the family and the Slate. Man was made for society, and justice has a natural basis. Men are united in social fellowship : all being God's creatures, they should observe contracts, abstain from mutual ham), and combine to protect one another from injury. Even the tie of common humanity demands, not only just dealing, but an active benevolence and kindness. The extension of the Roman Empire approximately realised the dream of one world-wide commonwealth for civilised mankind, its members bound each to each by civil law, if not by the law of nature. The idea of an immutable law, emanating from God, reason or nature, was clearly apprehended and assimilated by the Roman Stoics. of'naiutc. ^^ divine and eternal, this law of nature is valid for all at all times and places, and is superior in authority to any positive legislation that may conflict with it. Or again, as Cicero puts it, it is the utterance of that supreme reason which is implanted in the mind of each man at birth, and, when duly developed, enjoins unmistakeably what he should or should not do {reda ratio in iubendo el uttando, De Legibus, i 33). From Cicero onwards, through a long succession of lawyers more avowedly Stoical, this conception guided Roman jurisprudence and through the praetor's edict influenced legislation. In the ius gentium, developed to meet the practical needs of intercourse with foreigners, Rome , already possessed the germ of a law common to all nations. The great jurists of the Empire exerted themselves to bring it into conformity with what, in their judgement, a universal code should be, id quod naturalis ratio apud omnes homines (onslituit. Thus, the positive ordinances and customs of actual society were gradually merged in the rational law of an ideal community. Before the rise of imperial Rome the narrow limits of the City-State had been transcended in consequence of Alexander's conquests, and that cosmopolitan spirit, which external causes contributed to foster, exactly corresponded with the precepts of philosophy. For the later Roman Stoics we have in Latin the writings of Seneca (^991-5) and in Greek the discourses of Epictetus reported by Arrian and the meditations of the Emperor Marcus Aurelius Antoninus. Seneca (who died in 65 a.d.) was, like most Roman Stoics, an eclectic'. He is our earliest authority (belonging to the School itself) whose writings have come down to us at Rrst-hand and not in fr^ments or translations, but they are of little scientific value, partly from his eclecticism, partly from his mode of treatment. Under whatever title, dialogues, treatises, epistles, his works are substantially moral essays on practical themes. The Naturales Quaestiones form an exception : in them, by precept and example, the author recommends the contemplation of the wonders of nature as a means of elevating the mind. When Seneca ' II is an inlere^ting fad ihal two of his philosophical teachers, Soiion and rapfrius Fabianiu, were 'adherenis of the one avowedly independenl school which claimed lo be of native Roman origin. Its founder, Quintus Sextius Niger {horn aboul 70 B.C.), seems to have confined his originality lo combining Pythagorean elements with a variation on Stoicism, into which he infused a fresh vigour of moral leal and a conlempl for useless dialectics. Seneca, who several limes mentions him, describes him, in spite of his own denial, as a Stoic [Ep. 64). does touch upon the theoretical side of - Stoicism, it is in the hope of finding some novelty to interest his readers and almost in the spirit of antiquarian research, quae scire magis iuual quam predest {£pp. 58, 65, 89, 106). In short, his mission was Co the reason and conscience of men, but it was no part of his ambition to be a thinker himself, or to make thinkers of others. Indifference to exact scientific theory and willingness to accept good moral teaching from any quarter, from Plato or Epicurus as readily as from Chrysippus, is not peculiar to Seneca, it is the common characteristic of all writers of this period. To be over-curious on speculative questions is generally regarded as reprehensible, as diverting the attention of the individual from the all-important task of his own moral improve- ment. Here it is worth while to note how important has become the conception of the moral life as a pilgrimage, a progress Progremi towards virtue and away from folly and vice {progressio ad «<n™tdi uirtutem, trpoKtnrq). In the eyes of the earlier Stoics, who ^ '""' claimed wisdom for themselves and expected others to attain to it, such a state of probation was a concession to individual weakness, and, after all, the probationer was involved in the same condemnation as the fool. How diderent this is in Seneca ! He does not claim to be a sage himself, he is only progressing towards wisdom, and he sadly recognises that this is the common condition of humanity. How are we to emerge from the misery and folly of the world ? The way to virtue is easy to find, but the life of one who treads it is a continual struggle with inward corruption. It is a campaign in which there is no repose, in preparation for which a man needs not only ascetic bodily exercise, meagre diet and coarse raiment, but the harder mental discipline of keeping a strict guard on his opinions and notions, and controlling his affections and desires. Opinions and notions, affections and impulses are in our own power (ru ii^ ijt^tv) ; external circumstances, our bodies, wealth and position in the world are not in our power (ra oIk t'ft ijnir). By constant effort alone can we emerge victorious from the conflict, and build up a fixed habit and rational character. Philosophy, in the view of Seneca and Epictetus, comes to be regarded as the healer to whom men come from a sense of their weakness and disease, whose business is 'with the sick, not with the whole'. The wisdom by which she heals, needs no long dissertations or dialectical subtleties, but rather continual meditation and self-discipline. On the religious side may be noted a greater feeling of dependence upon God and the necessity of cheerfully submitting to the Divine will and acquiescing in the course of external events. 'Endurance and renunciation' is the motto of Epictetus, avixov vai iiir(;^ov : ' everything ', says Marcus Aurelius, ' is harmonious to me which is harmonious to Thee, O Universe '. The duties of philanthropy, mildness, and fo^iveness of injuries, are insisted upon. We should love men from the heart, love even those who have injured us, reflecting that they are kinsmen who err through ignorance. Tolerant judgement will be aided, if we bear in mind that he who hurts us by word or deed has acted on his own opinion, not outs, and that, if he does wrong, it is he who suffers, for he is the person deceived. It is not surprising to find an underlying vein of sadness in these Roman Stoics. Their moral earnestness made them realise the misery and folly of the actual world and the obstacles to a radical reform of human nature. In some directions, however, their efforts were not unsuccessful. In particular, their insistence on the duty of a more humane treatment of slaves led the way to that gradual amelioration of slavery throughout the Roman world which Christianity afterwards completed. Zellet's Philosophie der Griecktn, Vol. iii i (Dritter Thcil, Erstc Abtheilung), has been translated into English under the tides The Stoics, Bibiiocnphy. Epicureans and Sceptia,a.'aA The History of Eclecticism in Greek Philosophy. For Stoicism consult also Grant's essay in The Ethics 0/ Aristotle, Vol. i; for the ancient aulhorities on Epicurus, Usener's Epicures, 1887; for Lucretius, the edition of H. A. J. .Munra, the more recent Italian edition of Giussani, 1896, Guyau, La morale d'ipicure, 1878, J. Masson, .^/offtiV Theory 0/ Lucretius, 1%^^ and Lucretius, Epicurean and Poet, 1907-9; for Cicero, Madvig's De Finibus, Reid's Aeademica, J. B. Mayor's De Nalura Deorum ; for Seneca and later Stoics, Martha, £m moralistes sous tempire romain, ed. 5, 1886, Bonhoefler, Epictet und die Stoa, 1890, and Die Ethik des Stoikers EpicUt, 1894, S. Dill, Roman Society from Nero lo Marcus Aurelius, 1904. For Stoicism and Epicureanism, cp. also J. Adam's Texts. ..on Greek Philosophy after Aristotle, 1902, and R. D. Hicks, Stoic and Epicurean (with select biblio- graphy), igio.