Grice e Casini: l'implicatura conversazionale del naturismo – il concetto di natura a Roma -- filosofia italiana – Luigi Speranza
(Roma). Filosofo italiano. Grice: “I like Casini – he takes, unlike me, physics
seriously! But then so did Thales, according to Aristotle! – At Clifton we did
a lot of ‘physical’ rather than ‘metaphysical’ education!” – Linceo. Studia a
Roma sotto Nardi, Antoni, e Chabod. Si laurea sotto Spirito (disc. Gregory) con
“L'idea di natura”. I suoi interessi di ricerca in storia della
filosofia si sono successivamente estesi all'intreccio tra filosofia e scienze
sperimentali nel Settecento, soprattutto attorno alla figura di Isaac Newton e
alla diffusione della sintesi newtoniana nella cultura filosofica europea, a
proposito di filosofi come D'Alembert, Buffon, Maupertuis, Clairaut, Eulero,
non senza tener conto dell'opera divulgativa di Voltaire, fino a collocare in
tale contesto Kant. Insegna a Trieste, Bologna, e Roma. Le sue
ricerche riguardano Diderot e la filosofia dell'illuminismo, i nessi tra
rivoluzione scientifica e riflessione filosofica, l'origine e diffusione della
fisica di Newton, le vicende del mito pitagorico tra "prisca
philosophia" e "antica sapienza italica", le dispute sorte
attorno al darwinismo. Altre opere: “Diderot "philosophe",
Laterza); Mecanicismo -- L'universo-macchina: origini della filosofia
newtoniana, Laterza); Rousseau, Laterza); Introduzione all'illuminismo,
Laterza -- razionalismo); Newton e la coscienza europea (Il Mulino); “Progresso
ed utopia” (Laterza); “L'antica sapienza italica. Cronistoria di un mito” (Il
Mulino); “Hypotheses non fingo” (Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura); “Alle
origini del Novecento: "Leonardo", rivista filosofica di Firenze (Il
Mulino); Il concetto di creazione (Il Mulino). La lista di
autorità e l’accenno alla filosofia nazionale preludono al Platone. --Paolo
Casini. Si tratta di un saggio dedicato all'evoluzione del mito
pitagorico nella cultura europea. Senza cadere mai nella rassegna erudita,
l'autore segue passo passo le trasformazioni del mito dalla sua prima
incarnazione nella cultura romana alla riscoperta operata nel Rinascimento,
alle discussioni storico-archeologiche e alle strumentalizzazioni
politiche del Sette-Ottocento. Giuseppe
Bottai o delle ambiguità (Un'erma bifronte - Leader revisionista - Nella babele
corporativa - La guerra di Pisa - «Starci con la mia testa» - Apologia –
Espiazione) - 2. Ugo Spirito: «scienza» e «incoscienza» (Una teoresi
postidealista - Teorico dell'economia corporativa - Il «bolscevico» epurato -
«Mutevolezza e instabilità» - «Scienza», «ricerca», «arte» - Guerra e
Dopoguerra - Alla ricerca del padre) - 3. Camillo Pellizzi: il fascio di Londra
e la sociologia (Genius loci - Tra Roma e Londra - Pax romana in Albione -
«Aristòcrate» - Dottrina del fascismo - Il postfascismo e la «rivouzione mancata»
- Verso la sociologia) - 4. I doni di Soffici («Si parla» - «Scoperte e
massacri» - Sguardi retrospettivi: tragedia e catarsi - Docta ignorantia -
«Commesso viaggiatore dell'assoluto» - Genus irritabile vatum - Un dialogo tra
sordi - Amici e nemici) - 5. Un autoritratto (A metà ventennio – Riflessi - Tra
casa e scuola - Agrari in Toscana - I primi pedagoghi - L'Istituto Massimo sj -
Vinceremo! - Il passaggio del fronte – Dopoguerra - Scuola a Firenze - Al Liceo
Tasso) - 6. Studium Urbis (Gli anni Cinquanta - Nardi e Chabod - Eredità
idealistiche - Ideologie in crisi – Diderot - Roma, gli amici - Savinio,
Carocci - La naja – Intermezzi - Olivetti, Ivrea - La "cultura" della
RAI – Let Newton Be - Anni di prova) - Indice dei nomi Order
Zoogonia e "Trasformismo" nella fisica epicurea Giornale
Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 17 (n/a): 178. 1963. Like Recommend Bookmark
L'universo-Macchina Origini Della Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. 1969. 1
citation of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 10 Zev Bechler, Newton's
Physics and the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution. Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer (review) British Journal for the History of
Science The "Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes of ideology Rivista di
Filosofia Political Theory Like Recommend Bookmark Éléments de la philosophie
de Newton (review) British Journal for the History of Science Isaac Newton Like
Recommend Bookmark 10 Rousseau e l'esercizio della sovranità Rivista di
Filosofia Jean-Jacques Rousseau Like Recommend Bookmark 9 Il momento
newtoniano in Italia: un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 2.
2006. Like Recommend Bookmark 5 Newton in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia
Newton 1 citation of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie
Arouet de Voltaire, Éléments de la philosophie de Newton, critical edition by
Robert L. Walters and W. H. Barber. The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15. Oxford:
Voltaire Foundation, Taylor Institution, British Journal for the History of
Science 17th/18th Century French Philosophy Like Recommend Bookmark Lo spettro
del materialismo e la "Sacra famiglia" Rivista di Filosofia Lumi e
utopie in uno studio di Bronislaw Baczko Rivista di Filosofia The New World and
the Intelligent Design Rivista di Filosofia Anti-Darwinist ApproachesDesign
Arguments for Theism Like Recommend Bookmark Scienziati italiani del Seicento e
del Settecento Rivista di Filosofia Kant e la rivoluzione newtoniana Rivista di
Filosofia Kant: Philosophy of Science Like Recommend Bookmark » Ottica,
astronomia, relatività: Boscovich a Roma (1738-1748).« Rivista di Filosofia Introduzione
All'illuminismo da Newton a Rousseau Laterza. 1973. Like Recommend Bookmark
Newton e i suoi biografi Rivista di Filosofia Diderot e Shaftesbury Giornale
Critico Della Filosofia Italiana L'iniziazione Pitagorica Di Vico Rivista di
Storia Della Filosofia 4. 1996. Like Recommend Bookmark Per Conoscere Rousseau
with Jean-Jacques Rousseau Mondadori. 1976. Jean-Jacques Rousseau Toland e l'attività
della materia Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia British Philosophy, Misc
L'eclissi della scienza' Rivista di Filosofia Rousseau, il popolo sovrano e la
Repubblica di Ginevra Studi Filosofici Il mito pitagorico e la rivoluzione
astronomica Rivista di Filosofia Newton, Leibniz e l'analisi: la vera storia
Rivista di Filosofia 24 397. 1982. Like Recommend Bookmark 13 Francesco
Bianchini (1662-1729) und die europäische gelehrte Welt um 1700 Early Science
and Medicine History of Science Like Recommend Bookmark L'antica Sapienza
Italica Cronistoria di Un Mito. 1998. Pythagoreans Like Recommend
Bookmark 16 Candide, Theodicy and the «Philosophie de l'Histoire» Rivista
di Filosofia La filosofia a Roma Rivista di Filosofia Vico's initiation into
the study of Pythagoras Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia
Pythagoreans Topic Order Teoria e storia delle
rivoluzioni scientifiche secondo Thomas Kuhn Rivista di Filosofia Il problema D'Alembert Rivista di Filosofia
Semantica dell'Illuminismo Rivista di Filosofia Cheyne e la religione naturale
newtoniana Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana Newton's Physics and the Conceptual Structure
of the Scientific Revolution (review) British Journal for the History of
Science Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark 1 Diderot and the portrait
of eclectic philosophy Revue Internationale de Philosophie Diderot Like
Recommend Bookmark 6 "Magis amica veritas": Newton e Descartes
Rivista di Filosofia Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark La Natura Isedi.
1975. Like Recommend Bookmark Voltaire, la geometria della visione e la
metafisica Rivista di Filosofia Leopardi apprendista: scienza e filosofia
Rivista di Filosofia Studi stranieri sulla filosofia dei Lumi in Italia Rivista
di Filosofia Il metodo di Foucault e le
origini della rivoluzione francese Rivista di Filosofia Rousseau e Diderot
Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Diderot « philosophe » Revue Philosophique de
la France Et de l'Etranger Continental Philosophy 1 citation of this work Like
Recommend Bookmark Newton: gli scolii classici Giornale Critico Della Filosofia
Italiana La ricerca embriologica in Italia da Malpighi a Spallanzani Rivista di
Filosofia L'empirismo e la vera
filosofia: il caso Scinà Rivista di Filosofia 8The Newtonian moment in Italy: A
post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Classical Mechanics Like
Recommend Bookmark 6 James, Freud e il determinismo della psiche Rivista
di Filosofia Freud Grean: Shaftesbury's philosophy of religion and ethics. A
study in enthusiasm (review) Studia Leibnitiana
Herschel, Whewell, Stuart Mill e l'«analogia della natura» Rivista di
Filosofia Newton: the classical scholia History of Science 22 (1): 1-58. 1984.
1 reference in this work 15 citations of this work Like Recommend Bookmark
Diderot et le portrait du philosophe éclectique Revue Internationale de
Philosophie Morte e trasfigurazione del testo Rivista di Filosofia
L'universo-Macchina Origini Della Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. Bechler,
Newton's Physics and the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution. Boston
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer (review) British
Journal for the History of Science Éléments de la philosophie de Newton
(review) British Journal for the History of Science 2Isaac Newton Like
Recommend Bookmark 6 The "Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes of
ideology Rivista di Filosofia Political Theory Il momento newtoniano in Italia:
un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Rousseau e l'esercizio della
sovranità Rivista di Filosofia
Jean-Jacques Rousseau Topic Order 5 Newton
in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia saac Newton 1 citation of this work Like
Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie Arouet de Voltaire, Éléments de la
philosophie de Newton, critical edition by Robert L. Walters and W. H. Barber.
The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, Taylor
Institution, (review) British Journal
for the History of Science 26 (3): 360-361. 1993. 17th/18th Century French
Philosophy. Grice: “An assumption generally shared by those who wrote and read
the tests surveyed in Latin is that male desire can normally and normatively be
directed at either male of female objects. If this configuration is held to be
NORMAL or NORMATIVE, we might expect that it would also be represented as
NAATURAL, and it is thus worthwhile to consider the role played by the
discourse of NATURE in ancient representations of sexual behaviour. This
question is both hughe and complex.Important discussions include Boswell,
1Foucault, 1986, 150-7, 189-227, and Winkler, 20-1 36-7 114 8. but one thing is
clear: the ancient rhetoric of nature, as it relates to sexual practices,
displays significant differenct from more recent discourses. Boswell, for
example, observes that while “what is supposed to have been the major
contribution of Stoicism to Christian sexual morality – the idea that the sole
‘natural’ and hence moral use of sexuality is procreation, is in fact a common
belief of amny philosophies of the day’ at the same time, ‘the term UNNATURAL
was applied eto everything from POSTNATAL CHILD SUPPORT to legal contracts
between friends (Boswell, 129, 149 cf. 15: ‘The objection that homsosexuality
is ‘unnatural’ appears, in short, to be neither scientifically nor morally
cogent and probably represents mnothing more than a derogatory epithet of unusual
emotiona impact due to a confluence of historically sanctioned prejudiced and
ill-formed ideas about ‘nature.’”Thus, as Winkler notes, the contrast between
nature and non-nature, when deployed in ancient writings simply ‘does not
posess the same valence that it does today’ Winkler, p. 20 Moreover, nearly all
of the texts that offer opinions on whether specific secual practice is in
accordance with nature are works of philosophy. The guestion does NOT seem to
have seriously engaged the writers of texts that directly spoke to and
reflected popular moral conceptions (e. g. graffiti, comedies, epigram, love
poetry, oratory). For this important distinction between the morallyity
espoused by a philosopher and what we might call popular morality, see the
introduction and chapter 1. In short, as
Richinlin warns us, the question I ‘something of a red herring, since the
concept of nature takes a larger and more ominous form in our Christian culture
than it did in AAncient Rome, whetere itw as a matter for philosophers’.Richlin,
p. 533. But it may nonetheless be worthwhile to attempt a preliminary
exploration of how the rhetoric of NATURE was applied by some ROMAN
PHILOSOPHERS to sexual practices, particularly those between males.In other
words. I would like to go a step or two beyond that ‘nature’ is generally used
by Roman moralists to justify what they approve of’ (Edwards 88 n. 87). always
bearing in mind, however, that to the extent that it was mostly taken up by
philsoeophers, the question of ‘natural’ sexual practice seems not to have
played a significant role in most public discourse among Romans.
Nonphilosophical texts sometimes do deploy the rhetoric of NATURE in
conjunction with sexual practices, at least insofras they as they offer
representations of ANIMAL bheaviour, one possible component in arguments about
what is natural.2-6, and Win3, on Philo’s description of crocodiles mating.
kler, 2See for example Boswell, 137-43, 15 It will come as no surprise that
Roman writers images of animals’ sexual practices are transparetntly influenced
by their own cultural traditions. Thus in no Roman text do we find an explicit
appeal to animal bhehaviour in order to condemn sexual practices between males
as unnatural.Such an argument does occasionally appear in Greek texts, such as
Plato, Laws 836c (martua parag Omenos en ton therios phusin kai deiknos pros ta
toitauta oux aptomenon arena arrenos dia to me phusei touto einai – and Lucian
Amores 36. To Be sure, Musonius Ruffus’s condemnation of sexual practices
between males as para phusin might imply a reference to animal practices, and
it is possible that in some work now lost to us the Roman Stoic followed in
Plato’s footsteps in being explicit on the point. A Juvenalian satire does make
reference to animal behaviour in orer to condemn cannibalism (claiming that no
animas eat member s of their own species Juv. 15 159-68. And in a passage
discussed later in this appendix, Ovid has a character argue that NO FEMALE
ANIMAL experiences SEXUAL DESIRE for other females. These claims are as
unsupportable as the claim that sexual practices between males do not occur
anong nonhuman animals.This is obvious to anyone who has spent time with dogs.
With regard to the academic-study of the question, the remarks of Wolfe,
Evolution and Female Primate Sexual Behaviour, in Understanding behaviour: what
primate studies tell us about human behaviour Oxford, p. 130 are as
illuminating as they are depressing. ‘I have taked with several (anonymous at
their request) primatologists who have told me that they have observed both
male and female homosexual bheaviour during field studies. They seemed
reluctant t publish their data, however,
either because THEY FEARED HOMOPHOBIC REEACTIONS (‘my ccolleagues might thank
that I am gay’) or because they lack a framework for analysis (‘I don’t know
what it means’). On the latter point Wolfe insightfully comments that the same
problem affects our attempts to understand ANY sexual interactions among
primates. ‘Because the alloprimates do not possess language, it is impossible
to inquir into their sexual eroticism. In other words, homosexual and
heterosexual behaviours can be observed, recorded, and analysed, but we cannot
infer either homoeroticism or heteroeroticism from such behaviours (p. 131). But
the fact that we do find animal behaviour cited by Roman authors to CONDEMN
such phenomena as cannibalism and same-sec desire among females, but not
SAME-SEX desire among males, merely proves the point. These rhetorical
strategies reveal more about ROMAN cultural concerns than about actual animal
behaviour. A poem in the Appendix Vergiliana introduces us to a lover hhappyly
separated from his beloved Lydia. In the throes of his grief he cries out that
this miserable fate NEVER BEFALLS ANIMALS: A bull is never without his cor, nor
a he-goat without his mate. In fact, sighs, the lover: ET MAS QUACUMEQUE EST
ILLA SUA FEMINA IUNCAT INTERPELLATOS SUMPAUQM PLORAVIT AMORES CUR NON ET NOBIS
FACILIS NAUTRA FUISTI CUR EGO CRUDELEM PATIOR TAM SAEPE DOLOREM? (Lydia 35-8). The
lover is melodramatically weepy and that consideration partially accounts of
his ridiculous claim that male animals are never to be seen without their
mates. Still, amatory hyperbole aside the verses nicely illustrate the tendency
to shape both natura and animal bheaviour into whatever form is convenient for
the argument at hand. Thus, Ovid,s suggesting that the best way to appease
one’s angry mistress is in bed, portrays sexual behaviour among early human
beings and animals s as the primary force that effects RECONCILIATION (Ars 2
461-92. The poet offers a lovely panorama in which animal behaviour is invoked
as a POSTIIVE paradigm for specific human practices: unting otherwise scattered
groups (2. 473-80) and mollifying an angry lover (2. 481-90). Less than two
hundred lines later, the same poet invokes animalas as A NEGATIVE PARADIGM,
again in support of a characteristically human concern: discretion in sexual
matters. IN MEDIO PASSIMQUE COIT PECUS HOC QUOQUE VISO AVETIT VULTUS NEMPE
PUELLA SUOUS CONVENIUNS THALAMI FURTIS ET IANUA NOSTRIS PARSQUE SUB INJIECAT
VESTE PUDDAN LATET ET SI NON TENEBRAS AT QUIDDAM NUBIS OPACAE QUAERIMUS ATQUE
ALIQUID LUCE PATENTE MINUS (Ovid, Ars, 2 615-20). Drawing his objets lesson to
a close, Ovid holds up his own behaviour as a pattern to follow. NOS ETIAM
VEROS PARCE PROFITEMUR AMORES TECTAQUE SUNT SOLIDA MYSTIFCA FURTA FIDE 639-40.
And we are reminded of the strategies of this pasage’s broader context. If you
want to keep your girlfriend happy, do not kiss and tell: that is the argument
in service of which animal behaviour is invoked as NEGATIVE paradigm. These to
Ovidian passages illustrate the utilyt of arguments from the animal world. Just
look ant the animals and see how much we resemble them; just look at the51-5. animals and see how far we have come.An
epigram by theGreek poet Strato gives the later poin an dineresting twist. We
huam beings, he writes, are SUPERIOR to animals in that, in addition to vaginal
intercourse, we have discovered ANAL INTERCOURSE, thus men who are dominated by
women are really no better than mere animals (A P 12 245 PAN ALOGON soon bivei
monon oi ligkoi de ton allon zoon tout exkomen to pleon pugizein eurotntes
hosoi de guanxi kratountai ton alogon zoon ouden exousi kleon. It all depends
on the eye – and rhetorical needs – of the beholder. OS it is that Roman
writers show how Roman they are through the picture they paint of sexual
practices among animals of the same sex. Ovid himself, in his Metamorphoses,
imagines the plight of young girl named Iphis who has fallen in love with
another girl. In a torrent of self-pity and self-abuse, she expostulates on her
passion, making a simultaneous appeal to NATURA and to the animals that is
reminiscent of Ovid’s sweeping review of animal bheaviour in the Ars amatorial
just cited. But this time the paradigm is an emphatically negative one. SI DI
MIHI PARCERE VELLENT PARCERE DEBUERANT SI NON ET PERDERE VELLENT NAUTRALE MALUM
SALTEM ET DE MORE DEDISSENT NEC CACCAM VACCA NEC EQUAS AMOR URIT EQUARUM: URIT
OVES ARIES SEQUITUR SUA FEMINA CERVUM SIC ET AVES COEUNT INTERQUE ANIMALIA
UNCTA FEMINA FEMINEO ONREPTA CUPIDINE NULLA EST (Ov. Met. 9. 728-34) As with
Lydia’s lover, so here we have the melodramatic expostulations of an unah[py
lover, and similarly her view of animal behaviour does not correspond to the
realities of that behaviour. Still, these arguments are pitched in such a way
as to invite a Roman reader’s agreement, and the sexual practices invoked as
natural and occurring among the animals demonstrate a SUSPICIOUS SIMILARTY to
the sexual practices and desired SEMMED ACCEPTABLE BY ROMAN CULTURE (the female
never leaves the male, heterosexual intercourse is a convenient and pleasurable
way of unting different social groups, and females never lust after females),
or to specifically HUMAN EROTIC STRATEGIES: we do not copulate in public, and
we should not kiss and tell if we want our to keep our partners happy. It
cannot be coincidental that, whereas Ovid invokes animal behaviour in the
context of a girl’s tortured rejection of her own passionalte yearnings for
another girl, the mythic compendium in which this natrratie is found is
peppered with stories involves passion and sexual relations between males. Both
Orfeo (after losing his wife Euridice) and the gods themselves (whether married
or not) are represented as ‘giving over their love to TENDER MALES, harvesting
the BRIEF springtime and its first flowers before maturaity sets in” Ov. Met.
10. 83-5 ORPHEUS ETIAM THRACUM POPULIS FUIT AUCTOR AMORET IN TENEROS TRANSFERRE
MARES CITRAQUE IUVENTAM AETATIS BREVE VER ET PRIMOS CARPERE FLORES. The stories
that Orfeo proceeds ts to relate include those of the young CYPARISSUS once
loved by Apollo Met 10.106-42 and the tales of Zeus and Ganumede, Apollo and
Hyacinth (Met 10 155-219 Consider also the beautiful sixteen yer old Indian boy
Athis and his Assyrian lover Lycabas (Met. 5 47-72. A passage which echoes of
Virgil’s lines on NISUS AND EURIALO discussed in chapter 2. And the remark that
the stunning but haughty young Narcissus, also in his sixteenth year, had many
admireers of both sexses (Met 3 351-5.None of Ovid’s characters arever
questions the NATURAL status of that kind of erotic experience or invokes the
animals in order to reject it. Aulus Gellius preserves for us some anecdotes
that further demonstrate the manner in which animal bheaviour could be made to
conform to human paradigms. Writing of (IMPLICITLY MALE) dolfns who fell in
love with beautiful boys (one oft them even died of a broek heart after losing
his beloved) Gellius exclaims that they were acing “in amazing human ways” 606C-D
and Plin N H 8 25-8 for this and other tales of male dolphins falling in love
with human boys. Gell 6 8 3 NEQUE HI AMAVERUNT QUOD SUNT IPSI GENUS SED PUEROS
FORMA LIBERALI IN NAVICULIS FORE AUT IN VADIS LITORUM CONSPECTOS MIRIS ET
HUMANIS MODIS ARSERUNS. Cf. Athen 13 Once again, the comment tells us more
about ‘human ways’ than about dolphins. The elder Plini, who alo relates this
story regarding the dolphin, introduces his encyclopeic discussion of elephants
by observing that they are nonly the largest land animals but the ones closest
to human beings in their intelligence and sense of morality. In particular,
they take pleasure in love and pride (AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS), and by way
of illustration of the ‘power of love’ (AMORIS VIS) among elephants he cites two
examples: ONE MALE FELL IN LOVE WITH A FEMALE FLOWER_SELLER, another with a
young Syractusan man named MENANDER who was in Ptolemy’s army. Likehise he
tells of a MALE GOOSE who fell in love with a beautiful young Greek MAN, and of
another who loved a female musician whose beauty as such that she alstro
attracted the attention of a ram. -4. NEC QUIA DESIT ILLIS AMORIS VIS, NAMQUE
TRADITUR UNUS AMASSE QUANDAM IN AEGYPTO COROLLAS VENDENTEM ALLUS MENANDRUM
SYRACUSANUM INCIPIENTIS IUVENTAE IN EERCITU PTOLEMACI DESIDERIUM EIUS QUOTIENS
NON VIDERET INEDIA TESTATUS 10.51 QUIN EST FAMA AMORS AEGII DILECTA FORMA PUERI
NOMINE OLENII AMPHILOCHI, ET GLAUCES PTOLOMAEO REGI CITHARA CANENTIS QUAM EODEM
TEMPORE ET ARIES AMASSE PRODITUR. Plin N H 8 1. MAXIMUM EST EPLEPHANS PROXIMUMQUE
HUMANIS SENSIBUS QUIPPE INTELLECTUS ILLIS SERMONIS PATRII ET IMPERIORUM
OBEDIENTIA, OFFICIOURM QUAE DIDICERE MEMORIA, AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS 8 13Turing
to the concept of NATURA as it applied to sexual pracyices by ancient writers,
we being with basica basic problem. The very term NATURA has various referents
in those texts. Sometimes NATURA seems simply to refer to the way things are or
to the INHERENT nature OF something, sometimes to the way things SHOULD be according
to the intention ordictates of some transcendent imperative. Thus Foucault
speaks of ‘the ‘three axes of nature’ in philosophical discourse. The general
order of the world, the orgginal state of mankind, and a behaviour that is
reasonably adapted to natural ends.Fouctault, p. 215-6. See also the
discussions in Boswell, p. 11-5, where he distinguishes between ‘realistic’ and
‘ideal’ notions of nature, Beagon, and Levy, “Le concept de nature a Rome: la
physique, Paris). The first two of these axes are evident in a wife-variety of
Roman texts. Departures from what is observably the usual PHYSICAL constitution
of various thbeings could be called NONNATURAL or UNNATURAL even by
nonphilosophical authors. The Minotuar, centaurs, a snake with feet, a bird
with four wings, and a sexual union between a woman (the muthis Pasiphae) and a
bull.snAnon De Differentiis 520 23 MONSTRUM EST CONTRA NATURAM UT EST
MINOTAURUS. Serv. Aen 6. 286 (centaurs) Suet Prata fr. 176.113-5 snakes with feet, birds with four wings.
Serv. Aen. 1. 235.11. Pasiphae and the bull. Te elder Plinty claims that breech
births are ‘against nature’ since it is ‘nature’s way’ that we should be born
head first.n N H 7 45 -6. IN PEDES PROCIDERE NASCENTEM CONTRA NATURAM EST RITUS
NATURAE CAPITE HOMINEM GIGNI MOST EST PEDIBUS EFFERRI. PLiQuintilian argues
that to push one’s hair back from the forehead in order to achieve some
dramatic effect is to act ‘against nature’.Quint I O 11 3 160 CAPILLOS A FRONTE
CONTRA NATURAM RETRO AGERE. and Seneca himself
opines that being carried about in a litter is ‘contra natural’a, since nature
has gives us feet and we should use them.Sen. Epist 55 ` LABOR EST ENIM ET DIU
FERI AC NESCIO AN EO MAIOR QUIA CONTRA NATURAM EST QUAE PEDES DEDIT UT PER NOS
AMBULAREMUS. Finally, the belief that physical disabilities and disease are
UNNAUTARAL, and thus, implicitly, that a healthy body displaying no marked
derivations from the form illustrates what nature designed or intended,
surfaces in a number of texts, arnign from Celusus’ mdical treatise to
Ciceroo’s philosophical works to declamations attributed to Quintilian, to a
moral epistle fo Seneca to the, to the Digest.2 1. 60 pr. MOTUS CORPORIS CONTRA
NATURAM QUAM FEBREM APPELLANT. Quint. Decld. Min. 298.12 WEAK AND MALFORMED
BODIES ARE IMPLICITLY CCONTRA NATURAM. Celsus Medic 3 21 15. On fluids that are
retained in the body contra naturam. Cic Off 3 30 MORBUS EST CONTRA NATURAM.
Gell. 4 2 3 Labeo defines morbus asHABITUS CUIUSQUE CORPORIS CONTRA NATURAM QUI
USUUM ETIUS FACIT DETERIOREM. Cf. D. 21 1 1 7. D. 4Along the same lines, some
ancient writers also suggest that to harm a healthy body with poisons and the
like is unnatural.Quint Decl. Min. 246.3 the plaintiff refers to a substance as
a venenum QUONIAM MEDICAMENTUM SIT ET EFFICIAT ALIQUID CONTRA NATURAM. Sen
Epist 5. 4. To torment one’s body and to eat unhealthy food is CONTRA NATURAM. As
for the third of the axes described by Foucault, anthropologists and others
have long observed that proclamations concerning practices that are in
acoordance with nature often turn out to reflect specific cultural traditions.
As Winkler puts it, for nature we may often read culture.Winkler p. 17. In the
same way Edwards p. 87-8 discusses a passage from Seneca (Epist 95.20=1)
discussed in chapter 5, having to do with women who violate their ‘nature.’ She
concludes that ‘Seneca was not reacting to naturally anomalous bheaviour. He was
taking part in the reproduction of a a cultural system.’ So too Veyne , p. 26.
‘When an ancient says that something is unnatural, he does not mean that it is
disgraceful (monstrueuse) that that it does not conform with the rules of
society, or that it is perverted OR ARTIFICIAL”. Roman sources of various types
certainly support that contention. Thus, for example, violations of traditional
PRINCIPLELS OF LANGUAGE AND RHETORIC which are surely among the most intensely
cutlrual of human phenomeno are SOMETIMES SAID TO BE UNNATURAL.Serv. Comm. Art
Don. 4 4 4 PLINIUS AUTEM DICIT BARBARISMUM ESSE SERMOVEM UNUM IN QUO VIS SUA
EST CONTRA NATURAM – Serv Aen. 4. 427. REVELLI NON REVULSI. NAM VELLI ET
REVELLI DICIMUS. VULSUS VERO ET REVULSUS USURPATUM EST TANTUM IN PARTICIPIIS
CONTRA NATURAM cf. Sen. Contr. 10, pr. 9 – tof the rhetorician Musa. OMNIA
USQUE AD ULTIMUM TUMOREM PERDUCTA UT NON EXTRA SANITATEM SED EXTRA NATURAM
ESSENT. One legal writer invokes the rhetoric of NATURA to justify the
principle of individual ownership (joint possession of a single object is said
to be CONTRA NATURAL.D. 41 2 3 5 CONTRA NATURAM QUIPPE EST UT CUM EGO ALIQUID
TENEAM TU QUOTE ID TENERE VIDEARIS. Interestingly, another jurist argues that
the principle underlying the institution of slavery – that one person can be
owned by another – is actually ‘unnatural’ (D. 1. 5. 4. 1. SERVITUS EST
CONSTITUTIO IURIS GENTIUM QUA QUIS DOMINIO ALIENO CONTRA NATURAM SUBICITUR. In
a Horatioan satire we read that NATURA sees it that no one is every truly the
‘master’ of the land that he legally owns, and Natura puts a limit on how much
one can inherit (Hor. Sat. 2. 2. 129-30, 2.3.178). Sallust describes the
violation of the cultural and more specifically philosophical tradition
priviliengy the SOUL over the BODY as UNNATRUAL.Sall. Cat. 2. 8. QUIVUS PROFECT
CONTRA NATURAM CORPUS VOLUPTATI, ANIMA OVERI FUIT. SALLUST. Likewise, practices
violating Roan ideologies of MASCULINITY are represented as INFRACTIONS NOT of
cultural tranditions s but of the natural order. Cicero’s philosophical tratise
DE FINIBUS includes a discussion of the parts and with some clarity functions
of the BODY that illustrates the relation between NATURE and MSASCULINITY with
some clarity Our bodily parts, Cicero argues, are PERFECTLY DESIGNED to fulfil
their functions, and in doing so they are in conformance with nature. But there
are certain bodily movesmesns NOT in accord with nature (NATURAE
CONGRUENTES> If a man were to walk on his hand or to walk backwyasds, he
would manifestbly be rejecgting his identity as a human and thuswould thus be
displayeing a ‘hattred of nature’ (NAUTRAM ODISSE). Cic Fin 5 35. CORPORIS IGITUR
NOSTRI PARTES TOTAQUE FIGURA ET FORMA ET STATURA QUAM APTA AD NATURAM SIT
APPARET. The claim that walking on one’s hand is unnatural nicely illustrates
the gap between ancient and more recent uses of the rhetoric of nature – cfr.
Dodgson). The next illustration Cicer o offers of bodily moveents not in accord
with natura concerns correctly masculine ways of deporing oneself. QUAMOBREM
ETIAM SESSIONES QUAEDAM ET FLEXI FRACTIQUE MOTUS, QQUALES PROTERVORUM HOMINUM
AUT MOLLIUM ESSE SOLENT, CONTRA NATURAM SUNT, UT ETIAMSI ANIMI VITIO ID
EVENIANT TAMEN IN CORPOMUTRAR MUTARI HOMINIS NATURA VIDEATUR ITAQUE A CONTRARIO
MODERATI AEQUABILESQUE HABITUS AFFECTIONS USUSQUE CORPORIS APTI ESSE AD NAUTRAM
VIDENTUR (Cic. Fin 5. 35-6. Deemed ‘agaist natture’ are certain ways of
carrying oneself that are ‘wanton’ and ‘soft,’ movements lthat, like walking on
one’s hand or stepping backwards, clasi the with thvident purporse of the
body’s various parts. Implicitly then, nature wills men’s bodies to move and to
function in certain ways. Men who violate these principles of masculine
comportment are acting BOTH EFFEMINATELY (as we saw in chapter 4, militia is a
standard metaphor for effeminacy) AND UNNATURALLLY. Cultural traditions
regarding masculinity – here, appropriate bodily gestures – are identified with
the natural order.Similar conddemnations of inappropriate bodily comportment,
marked as EFFEMINATE, abound: walking daintily, scratching the hair delicately
wih onefinger, and so on (see chapter 4 in general and see Gleason for a
general discussion of physiognomy and masculinity in antiquity. How, then is
the rheotirc of nature applied to same-sex practices? One scholar has recently
suggested that the elder Pliny describes men’s desires to be anally penetrated
as occurring ‘by crime against nature’ Taylor, p. 325. But that is probably a
misinterpretation of Pliny’s language. IN HOMINUM GENERE MARIBUS DEVERTICULA
VENERIS EXCOGIGATA OMNIA, SCLERE (or CCCELERE naturae FEMINIS VERO AOBRTUS Plin
N H 10 172. The phrase DEVERTICULA VENERIS which one might translate (by-ways
of sex’ or ‘sexual deviations’ is vague. There is no reason to think that it
refers to specifically, let alone exclusively, to the practice of being anally
penetrated. Moreover, the phrase SCELERA NATURA or SCELERE NATURAE, rather than
‘crime against nature,’ is most obviously transated as ‘crime OF NATURE,’ that
is, a crime perpetrated BY NATURE.This is indeed the way Plinio uses the phrase
elsewhere, noting that we ought to call earthquakes ‘moracles of the eart
rather than crimes of nature’ (NH 2 206 – UT TERRAE MIRACULA POTIUS DICAMU QUAM
SCLEREA NATURAE. See Beagon, p. 29. In other words (pace Taylor and Rackham
Loeb Classical Library translation, I take the genitive NATURAE to be
subjective rather than objective. I have not found any parallels for such an
objective use of a genitive noun dependent upon scelus. In any case, Pliny is
not implying that all sexual desires or practices between males are unnatural:
in this same treatise, significantly called the HISTORIA NAUTRALIS or Natural
Investigations’ he reports the story of a male elephant who fell passionately
in love with a young man from Syractuse as an illustration of the obviously
natural power of love of love (amoris vis) among elephants; likewise, he
reports the story of a gosse who loved a beautiful young man.Plin N H 8 13-4,
10.51More explicitly referring to those men who take pleasure in being
penetrated, the speaker in Juvenal’s second satire riducules menwho have
wilfully abandoned their claim on masculine status by weaking makeup,
participating in women’s religious festivals, and even taking husbands, and
notes with gratitude, that nature does not allow them gto give birth.Juv. 2 139
40. SED MELIUS QUOD NIL ANIMIS IN CORPORI IURIS NATURA INDULGET STERILES
MORTUNTUR. For Further discussion see Appendix 2. The orator Labienus decries
wealthy men who castrate their male prostitutes (EXOLETI, see chapter 2) in
order to render them more suitable for playing the receptice role in
intercourse. These men use their rinces in UNNATURAL WAYS (contra natural), and
the natural standard they they violate is apparently the principle that mature
males both should make use of the PENISES and should be IMPENETRABLE.Sen Contr.
10. 4 17. PRINCIPES VIRI CONTRA NATURAM DIVITIAS SUAS EXERCENT CASTRATORUM
GREGES HABENT EXOLETOS SUOS AD LONGIOREM PATIENTIALM IMPUDICITIAE IDONEI SINT
AMPUTANT. Firmicus Maternus refers to men’s desires to be penetrated as CONTRA
NATURAL (5. 2. 11), and Caelius Aurelianus’s medical wirtings also reveal the
assumption that men’s ‘natural’ sexual function is TO PENETRATE and not to be
penetrated.9 137. NATURALIA VENERIS OFFICIA. Cael. Aurel. Morb. Chron. 4 In
short, nature’s ditactes conveniently accorded with cultural traditions, such
as those discouraging men from seeking to be penetrated, or those deterring
them from engaging in sexual relations with other men’s wives: in a poem that
urges on its male readers the principle that NATURA places a limit of their
desires, Horace remocommends, as implicitly being in line with the requirement
of nature, that men avoid potentially dangerous affaris with married women and
stick to their own slaves, bh male and female.Hor. Sat. 1 2 111. NONNE
CUPIDINIBUS STATUAT NATURA MODUM QUEM … Se chapter 1 for further discussion of
this poem. Cf. Sat. 1. 4. 113-4: NE SEQUERER MOECHAS CONCESSA CUM VENERE UTI
POSEEM. In one of his Episles (122) Seneca provides a lengthy and revealing
discussion of ‘unnatural’ behavours that include a reference to sexual
practices among males. He beings, however, by despairing of ‘those who have
perverted the roles of daytime and nightime, not opening their eyes, weighed
down by the preceding day’s hangover, until night begins its approach. Sen
Epist 122 2 SUNT QUI OFFICIA LUCIS NOTISQUE PERVERTERINT NEC ANTE DIDUCANT
OCULOS HESTERNA GRAVES CRAPULA QUAM ADPETERE NOX COEPIT. These people are
objectionably not simply because of their overindulgence in goof and drink but
because they do not respect the proper function of night and day.Comparing them
to the Antipodes, mythincal beings who live n the opposite side of the globe,
he asks. Do you think these people know HOW to live when they don’t even know
WHEN to live? 122.3 HOS TU EXISTIMAS SCIRE QUEMADMODUM VIVENDUM SIT QUI
NESCIUNT QUANDO?and this pervesion of night and say, is, in the end, ‘unnatural’.
INTERROGAS QUOMODO HAEC ANIMAO PRAVITAS FIAT AVERSANDI DIEM ET TOTAM VITAM IN
NOCTEM TRANSFERENDI? OMNIA VITA CONTRA NAUTRAM PUGNANT, OMNIA DEBITUM ORDINEM
DESERUNT (Sen Epist. 122.5). He then proceeds to tick off a serioes of
bheaviour that are similarly CONTRA NATURAM. First, people who drink on an
empty stomach ‘live contrary to nature’ Sen. 122 6 NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA
NATURAM VIVERE QUI IEIUNI BIBUNT QUI VINUM RECIPIUNT INANIBUS VENIS ET AD CIBUM
EBRII TRANSEUNT. Young men nowadsays, Seneca continues, go to the baths before
a meal and work up a sewat by drinking heavily; according to them, only
hopelessly philistine hicks (patres familiae rustici … et verae volupatigs
ignari) save their drinking for after the meal.Sen Epist 122 6. ATQUI FREQUENS
HOC ADULESCENTIUM VITIUM EST QUI VIRES EXCOLUNT UT IN IPSO PAENE BALINEI LIMINE
INTER NUDOS BIBANT IMMO POTENT ET SUDOREM QUEM MOVERUNT POTIONIBUS CREBRIS AC
FERVENTIBUS SUBINDE DESTRINGAT POST PRANDIUM AUT CENAM BIBERE VULGARE ETS HOC
PATRIS FAMILIAE RUSTICI FACIUT ET VERA VOLUPTATIS IGNARI. The latter comment,
with its contrast between URBAN AND RUSTIC life, austerity and luxyry , is a
valuable reminder of us. The standard violated by those who drank betweofre
eating was what we would call a cultural norm. But for Seneca they were
violating the dicates of NATURE, abandoning the proper order (debitum ordinem)
of things. This important point bust be borne in mind as we turn to the next
practices that come under Seneca’s fire: NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA NATURAM
VIVERE QUI OMMUTANT CUM FEMINIS VESTEM? NON VIVUNT CONTRA NAUTRA QUI SPECTANT
UT PUERITIA SPENDEAT TEMPORE ALIENO? QUID FIERI CRUDELIS VEL VISERIOUS POTEST?
NUMQUAM VIR ERIT, UT DIU VIRUM PATI POSSIT? ET CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE SEXUS
ERIPUISSE DEBUERANT NON NE AETAS QUIDEM ERIPIET (Sen. Epist 122. 7). The
concept of the proper order is very much in evidence here, and here again the
order shows unmistakable signs of cultural influence. Just as those who turn
night into day or drink wine before they eat a meal are engaging in unnatural
activities, so men who wear women’s clothes live contrary to nature – yet what
could be more cultural than the designation of certain kinds of clothing as
appropriate only for men and others as appropriate only for women? Moving on to
his next point, Senceca continues to focus on extermal appearance. Men who
attempt to give the appearance of the boyhood that is in fact no longer theirs
also ‘live contrary to nature’. Again the order of things has been disrputed.
Boys should be boys, men should be men. But these particular men want to LOOK
like boys in order to find older male sexual partners to penetrate them. Such
is the thenor of Seneca’s decorous but blunt phrase, ‘so that he may submit to
a man for a long time’ (ut diu virum pati possit’). If we filter out Seneca’s
moralizing overlay, this detail gives us a fascinating fglimpse oat Roman
realities. These MEN scorned by Seneca acted upon the awareness that MEN would
be more likely to find them desirable if their bodies seemed like those of BOYS
(not men): young, smooth, irless. Moreover, the very fact that these men made
the effort suggests that th actual age of the beautiful ‘boys’ we always hear
of may not have mattered to their loveers so much as their youthful APPEARANCE.Cf.
Boswell, p. 29, 81. All of this is very much a matter of CONVENTION, of
CULtURAL traditions concerning the ‘proper order’ of things, but Seneca
insistently pays homage to NATURA.Cf. Winkler, p. 21. “Contrary to nature means
to Senea not ‘outside the order of the kosmos’ but ‘unwilling to conform to the
simplicity of the unadorned life’ and, in the case of sex, ‘going AWOL rom
one’s assigned place in the social hierarchy’”. The importance of this order is
especially clear in the climactic illustrations of those who live ‘contrary to
nature’. These are people who wish to see see roses in winter and employ
artificial means to grow lilies in the cold season; who grow orchards at the
tops of towers and trees under the roofs of their homes (this latter proving
Seneca to a veritable outburst ofm moral indignation)., and those who construct
their bathhouses over the waters of the sea Sen. Epist 122 21 NON VIVUNT CONTRA
NATURAM QUI FUNDAMENTA THERMARUM IN MARI IACIUNT ET DELICATE NATARE IPSI SIBI
NON VIDENTUR NISI CALENTIA STAGNA FLUCT AC TEMPESTATE FERIANTUR. Finally Seneca returns to the example of
unnatural practices that sparked the whole discussion: those who pervert the
function of night and day aengage in the ultimate form of unnatural behaviour (Sen
Epist 122 9 CUM INSTITUERUNT OMNIA CONTRA NATURAE CONSUETUDINEM VELLE NOVISSIME
IN TOTUM AB ILLA DESCISCUNT LUCET SOMNI TEMPUS EST QUIES EST NUNC EXERCEAMUR
NUNC GESTEMUR NUNC PRANDEAMUS. That the practice ofs of growing trees indoors,
of building bathhouses over the sea, and of sleeping by day and partying by
night should be considered unnatural makes some sense in relation to notions of
the ‘proper order’ of things. Plants should e outdoors, buldings should be on
dray land, and people should sleep at night. But that thes practices should be
cited as the most egregious examples of unnatural bheaviour – they constitute
the climax of Seneca’s argument – demontrastes just how wide the gap is between
ancient moralists and their modern counterparts on the question of what is
natural. With regard to mature men who seek to be penetrated by men, the third
of Seneca’s examples of unnatural behaviour, Seneca makes in passing a
surprising remark. CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE SEXUS ERIPUISSE DEBUERAT NON NE AETAS
QUIDEM ERIPIET? 122.7. The clear implication is that a nature man certainly
ought to be safe from ‘indignity’ (here a moralizing euphemism for
penetration), but ultimately the very fact that he is MALE, REGARDLESS OF HIS
AGE, ought to protect him. With with one pointed sentence, then, Seneca is
suggesting that MALENESS IN ITSELF IS IDEALLY INCOMPATIBLE WITH BEING
PENETRATED, and since sexual acts were almost without exception conceptualized
as REQUIRING penetration, this amounts to positing the exclusion of sexual
practices BETWEEN MALES from the ‘proper order’. This is a fairly radical
suggestion FOR A ROAM MAN TO MAKE, and Seneca was no doubt aware of that fact.
He slips the comment quietly into his discussion, makes the point rather subtly
(it makight ake a second reading even to REALISE IT IS THERE), and then instantly
moves on to other, less controversial arguments. FOR as opposed to Seneca’s
suggestion that EVERY MALE, even a boy, should somehow be ‘rescued’ from
‘indignity,’ the usual Roman system of protocols governing men’s sexual
behaviour required the understanding that A BOY is different from A MAN precisely
because they COULD BE penetrated without necessarily forfeiting EVERY CLAIM to
masculine or male status (see especially chapter 5 on this last point). But
Seneca, waxing Stoic, here voices a dissenting opinion, as does the first
century A. D. Stoic philosopher MUSONIUS RUFUS, in one of twhose treatises we
find the remark that sexual practices BETWEEN MALES are ‘against nature’
(‘para-physical’) Muson, Ruf. 86. 10 Lutz para phusin. The remark needs to be
be put in the context of Musonius’s philosophy of nature. According to
Musonious, every createure has its own
TELOS beyond the goal of simply being aalive En a horse would not b e fully
living up to its telos if all it did was to eat, drink, and copulate (106.25-7
Lutz)., while the TELOS or goal of a human being is to live the life or arete
or VIRTUS. Thus, “each one’s nature (phusis) leads him to his particular
virtuous quality (arete), so that it is is a reasonable conclusion that a human
being is living in accordance WITH nature NOT when he lives in pleasure, but
rather when he lives in virtue” 108.1-3 Lutz). Elsewhere he opines that human
nature (phusis – anthropine phusis, natura humana, Hume, Human Nature) is not
aimed at pleasure (hedone, 106.21.3 Lutz). Consequently, luxury (truphe) is to
be avoided in EVERY way, as being the cause of INJUSTICE (126.30-1 Lutz). By
implication, then, eating, drinking, and aopulating are not in themselves evil,
but they can easily become sgns of a life of luxury, and if those activities
aconstitute the goals of our existence, we are FAILING TO FULFIL OUR POTENTIAL
AS A HUMAN BEING, namely, the practice of virtue, or reason, and consequently,
not living IN ACCORDANCE WITH NATURE, but against her (paa phusin). Thus, as
part of a regime of SELF-CONTROL (MALENESS OR MASCULINITY AS SELF-CONTROL, not
addictive behaviour or weakness of the will) Musonius argues that a man should
engage in a sexual practice only within the context of marriage for the purpose
of begetting children. Any other sexual relation, even within marriage should
be avoided. T”Those who do not live licentiously, or who are not evil, must
think that only those sexual practices are justified which are consummated
within marriage and for the creation of children, since these pratcttices are
licit (NOMIMA). But such people must think that those sexual practices which
hunt for mere pleasure are unjust and illicit, even if they take place within
marriage. Of Other forms of intercourse, those committed in moikheia (I e. a
sexual relation with a freeborn woman under another man;s control) are the most
illicit. No more moderate than this is the INTERCOURSE OF MALES WITH MALES,
since it is a DARING ACT CONTRARY TO NATURE. As for those forms of intercourse
with with females apart from moikheia which are not licit (kaTa nomon) all of
these are too shameful, because done on account of a lack of self-control. If
one utside to behave temperately (TEMPERANTIA,
CONTINENTIA) one would not dare to have relations with a courtesan, nor with a
free woman outside of marriage, nor, by Zeus, with one’s own slave woman
(Musonius Rufus, 86.4-14 Lutz). As I argued in chapter 1, Musonius’s final
remark reveals the extent to which the sexual morality that he is preaching is
at odds with mainstream Roman traditions. Nor is his suggestion that men should
keep their hans off prostitutes and their own slaves the only surprising
statement to be found in the treatises attributed to Musonius. He elsewhere aargues
against the obviously widespread practices of giving up for adoption or even
exposing unwanted children (96-97 Lutz), of EATING MEANT (here he explicitly
contrasts himself with the many hoi polloi who live to eat rather than the
other way around (118-18-20 Lutz) or SHAVING THE BEARD (128.4-6 Lutz), of using
wet nurses (42.5-9 Lutz), and most appositely, of allowing husbands sexual
freedoms not granted to wives (96-8 Lutz). Thus his condemnation of sexual
practices between MALES is issued in the context of a condemnation of ALL
SEXUAL PRATICES other than those between husband and wife aimed at procreation
(strictly speaking, vaginal intercourse when the wife is ovulating) and also in
the context of a a suspicion of all luxury oand of pleasures beyond those
relating to the bare necessities of life. Thus he condemns sexual relations
between males as contrary to nature (the implication being that the two sexes
ARE DESIGNED TO UNITE WICH EACH OTHER IN THE CONTEXT OF MARRIAGE), while sexual
relations between malesand female outside of marriage are criticized as
‘illicit (para-noma) and as signs of lack of self-control. Here Musonius is
obviously manipulating the ancient contrast between law or convention (nomos)
and nature (phusis) and interprestingly procreative relations within marriage
are ultimately given his seal of approval not because they are more ‘natural’
than tother sexual practices, but because they are ‘licit’ or ‘conventional’
(nomima), just as adulterious relations are most ‘illicit’ of unconventional
(paranomotatai). In other words, Musonius invokes the rhetoric of nature only
by way of secondary support.. A male-male relation is no more ‘moderate’ than a
adulterious relationa dn anyway, he adds, they are ‘unnatural’. But a relation
between a man and another man’s wife, while implicitly ‘natural’,is in the end
more ‘illicit’ than a male-male relation. Even for the Stoic Musonious, NATURA
may NOT be the ultimate arbiter. Interestingly, when he describes sexual
practices between males as being against nature, Musonius does not appeal to
animal bheaviour as does Plato in his Laws (836c). Indeed, such an argument
sould have ill-suited Musonius’s argument elsewhere that humans are different
from other animals and should not takem them as a MODEL FOR BHEAVIOUR. Thus he
argues that wise men ill not attack in return if attacked – such revenge is the
province of MERE ANIMALS – 78.26-7 Lutz) – and that, while among animals an act
of copulation suffices to procude offspring, human beings should aim for the
lifelong union that is marriage (88.16-17 Lutz). Finally, there is an important
distinction to observe between Musonius’s remark concerning sexual practices
between males and later Christian fulminations against ‘the unnatural vice’
which came to be a code term for ‘sodomy’. On the one hand, Musonius did not go
so far as to condemn such relations as THE unnatural vice. Indeed, if we think
about the implications of his words, relations between MALES do not even
constitute the ULTIAMTE sexual crime. He declare that ADULTEROUS relations are
‘the most illicit of all’ (paranomotatai) and thus clearly more ‘illicit’ than
relations between males which are howevery ‘equally immoderate’. Furthermore
Musonius’s approach to the problem of sexual behaviour differs from later
Christian moralists in a fundamental respect. As Foucault puts it, according to
Musonius, ‘to withdraw pleasure from this form (sc. Of marriage, to detach
pleasure from the conjugal relation in order to propoeseother ends for it, is
in fact to debase the ESSENTIAL composition of the human being. The defilement
is not in the sexual act itself, but in the ‘debauchery’ that would dissociate
it from marriage, where it has its natural form and its rational purpose” Foucault
p. 170. Cicero ro in a passage from one of this major philosophical works, the
Tusculan disputations, approaches the ascetic stance advocated by Seneca and
Musonius Rufus, although he nowhere makes an explicit commitment to the extreme
suggested by Seneca and preached by Musonius. Speaking in the Tusculan
Disputations of the detrimental effects of erotic passion, Cicero observes that
the works of Greek poets are filled with images of love. Focusing on those who
describe LOVE FOR BOYS (he mentions Alcaeus, Anacreon, and Ibycus), Cicero notes
thain an aside that ‘NATURE HAS GRANTED A GREATER PERMISSIVENESS (maiorem
liicnetial)” to men’s affairs with women. Cic. Tusc. 4. 71. ATQUE UT MULIEBRIS
AMORES OMITTAM QUIVUS MAIOREM LICENTIAL NATURA CONCESSIT QUIS AUT DE GANYMEDI
RAPTU DUBITAT QUID POETAE VELINT AUT NON INTELLEGIT QUID APUD EURIPIDEM ET
LOQUATUR ET CUPIAT LAIUS. The comparative (MAIOREM LICENTIAL is noteworthy.
NATURE has granted ‘greater’, not exclusive license to affais with women than
to affairs with BOYS. The Latter are evidently NOT FORBIDDEN BY NATURE.
Discouraged perhaps, but not outlawed. This is a BEGRUDGING ADMISSION, in
perfect agreement with the tenor of the whole discussion of sexual passion
which had opened thus. ET UT TURPES SUNT QUI ECFERUNT SE LAETITIA TUM CUM
FRUUNTUR VENERIIS VOLUPTATIBUS SIC FLAGITIOSI QUI EAS INFLAMAMATO ANIMO
CONCPISCUNT TOTUS VERO ISTE QUI VOLGO APPELATUR AMOR – NEC HERCULE INVNEIO QUO
NOMINE ALIO POSSIT APPELARI TANTAE
LEVITATIS EST UT NIHIL VIDEAM QUOD PUTEM CONFERENDUM. (Cic. Tusc. 4. 68). These
words disparage sexual passion as a whole – particularly a hot, inflamed desire
(QUI EAST INFLAMMATO ANIMO CONCUSPICUNT) whether indulged in with women or with
boys. NATURA, according to Cicero, makes it easier to indulge in this passion
with women, so that when men DO INDULGE
IN IT WITH BOYS, they show just who DEEPLY THEY HAVE FALLEN VICTIM TO LOVE –
that treacherous and destructive power, ‘te originator of disgraveful behaviour
and inconstanty (FLAGITTI ET LEVITATIS AUCTOREM (4. 68), as G. Williams notes. In
fact, remarkably enough, Cicero later claims that love itself is not natural.
Cic. Tusc. 4 76. If love were natural, everyone would love, they would always
love, and would love the same thing: one person would not be deterred from
loving by a sense of shame, another by rational thought, another by his satiety
– ETENIM SI NAUTRALIS AMOR ESSET ET AMARENT OMNES ET SEMPER AMARENT ET IDEM
AMARENT NEQUE ALIUM PUDOR ALIUM COGITATIO ALIUM SATIETAS DETERRERET. Cicero’s
remark on NATURA and sexual relations with women is in fact fact little more
than a a passing comment. Still, its implications deserve some consideration.
In what whays does NATURE grant ‘greater permisiveness’ to a relation with aa
woma than with a boy? Why does Seneca suggest that men’s MALENESS ought to
preclude them from being PENETRATED, and why does Musonius Rufus condemn ALL
SEXUAL PRACTICES BETWEEN MALES as unnatural? These philosophers’ comments seem
to rest on certain assumptions about the function of sexual organs. Certainly
Seneca emphasixes the notion of the proper order or debitus ordon, according to
which men should not drink wine before eating, grow roses in the winter, build
buildings over the sea, or PENETRATE MALES. In short, some kind of ARGUMENT
FROM DESIGN seems to lruk in the backgrounf of Cicero’s Seneca’s and Musoniu’s
claism. The penis is ‘designed’ to PENETRATE a vagina. TA vagina is deigned to
be penetrated by a penis. Similarly the passage from Phaedrus Fables 4 16
discussed in chapter 5 implies, whitout actually using the word NATURA, that
males who desire to be penetrated (molles mares) and females who desire to
penetrate (tribades) have A FLAWED DESIGN. When Prometheus was assuming these
people’s bodies from CLAY, he attached the genial organs of the opposite sex in
a drunken slip-up. But his more popularizing account only specifies that those
males who DESIRE to be penetrated are anomalous. It does not designate those
men who seek to penetrate other males as unnatural. On this model, a sexual act
in which a master penetrated his UNWILLING MALE slave is NOT UNNATURAL. By contrast, according the
philosophers discussed here (Musonius most expliclty) this act would be
unnatural. But on the whole very few
Roman writers seem to have taken this kind of argument to heart. In general,
ROMAN MEN’S BEHAVIOURAL codes reflect an AWARENESS that the PENIS IS SUITED for
purposes OTHER than penetrating avagina, and that the vagina is NOT the only
organ suited for being penetrated. Such is the implication of a witty comment
in an epigram of Martial’s addressed to a man who, instead of doing the USUAL
WITHIN with his BOY and analyy penetrating him, has been STIMULATING THIS
GENITALS. This is objectionable because it will speed up the process of his
maturation and thus hasten THE ADVENT OF HIS BEARD (11.22.1-8). Martial tries
to talk some sense into his friend and the epigram ends with an APPEAL TO
NATURE. DIVISIT NATURA MAREM PARS UNA PUELLIS UNA VIRIS GENITA EST UTERE PARTE
TUA Mart 1 22.9-10. The comment is of course a witticigm. Note the logical
contradiction that this playful invocation of nature creates. If the penis is
designed by nature for girls and the anus for mmen,how can a man use a boy’s
anus in the way nature intended (i. e. to be penetrated by men) and at the same
time use his own penis in the way nature intended (i. e. by penetrating a girl?
See chapters 1 and 5 for further fsucssion of this epigram together with
Martial’s humorous invocation of the paradigm of nature with regard to
masturbation. but if the humour was to succeed, the notion that a boy’s anus is
designed by nature for a man to penetrate cannot have seemed outrageous to
Martial’s readership. After all, the rhetorical goal of the epigram is to steer
tha man onto the path of right behaviour, the path which Martial’s won persona,
dutifully, even proudly, followed. This sort of comment – rather than the
passing remarks of such philosophers as Cicero, Seneca and Musonius Rufus,
reflects the mainstreat Roman understanding of what constitutes NORMATIVE and
NATURAL sexual beavhiour for a boy and for a man. It is significant, moreover,
that neither CCicero nor Seneca nor Musonius Rufus nor any other survinving
Roman text, philosophical or not, argues that a MAN’s *DESIRE* to penetrate a
boy is ‘contrary to nature’. Musonius, for one, speaks ony of the sexual act
(SUMPLOKAI). We return to the Epicurean perspective offered by Lucretius cited
in chapter i. SIC IGITUR VENERIS QUI TELIS ACCIPIT ICTUS SIVE PUER MEMBRIS
MULIEBRIBUS HUNC IACULATUR SEU MULIEUR TOTO IACTANS E CORPORE AMOREM UNDE
FERITUR EO TENDIT GESTITQUE COIR ET IACERE UMOREM IN CORPUS DE CORPRE DUCTUM.
Lucr. 4. 1052-6. This are lines from a poem dedicated to teaching its Roman
readers about ‘the nature of things’ (de rerum natura 1.25). cf. Boswell p. 149
“Lucretius’s De rerum natura dealt with the whole of ‘natura’ but it was the
‘rerum’ of things – which suggested to Latin readers what modern speakers mean
by ‘nature’”. Obviously the SUSCEPTIBILITY OF MEN to THE ALLURE of boys and
women is a PART OF THE NATURAL ORDER for Lucretius. The beams of atomic
particles that EMANATE from the bodies of boys and women and attract men to
them are an integral part of the nature of things. It is the mentalitly evident
in such diverse textsa Lucretius’s poetic treatise On the nature of Things,
Martial’s epigrams, and graffiti scrawled on ancient walls that we need to keep
in mind when we evaluate the comments of Musonius Rufus, Seneca, and Cicero.
These are the words of three philosophers. Cicero expounding on the danger s of
love, Senceca inveighing against the corrputions of the world around him, and
Musonius arguing that men should engage only in certain kind of sexual
relations and only with their wives, the goal being the production of
legitimate offspring and not the pursuit of pleasure. These pronouncements tell
u something about the world in which these three philosophers who made them
lived, and about what men and women in that world were actually doing. Seneca
for example is hardly fulminating about imaginary fices) but they tells us even
more about Cicero, Seneca, and Musoiuns, and their own philosophical
allegiances We have every reason to believe that comments like their rpersented
a minoriy opinion. Indeed, the men AGAINST whom Musonius argues, who believed
that A MASTER has absolute power to do ANYTHING HE WANTS to his slave, is
precisel that man shoes VOICE dominated the public discourse on sexual
practice. Moreover, as Winkler (p. 21) trenchangly observers, Seneca’s
condemnation of such ‘unnatural’ behaviour as growing hothouse flowers or
throwing nightime parties, ‘though articulated as universal, is OBVIOUSLY
DIRECTED AT A VERY SMALL AND WEALTHY ELITE – THOSE WHO CAN AFFORD THE SORT OF
LUXURIES Seneca wants ‘ALL MANKIND’ to do without”, It is telling, too, that
Cicero himself never makes this kind of APPEAL TO NATURA in the SEXUAL
INVECTIVE sscattered throughout the speeches he delivered in the public arenas
of the courtroom, Senate, or popular assembly (see chapter 5), and that the argument
appears NOWEHERE ELSE IN the considerable corpus of Seneca’s moral treatises.
Likewise, it is worth noting that Musonius Rufus’s who makes the most extreme
case, not only wrote his treatise in GREEK rather than Latin, as if to
underscore its distance from he everyday beliefs and practices of Romans, but as
a philosopher omitted to stoicis in a way that Cicero and and Seneca are not. As
Haexter reminds us, Cicero proposes manydifferent rhetorical and philosophical
positions in his speeches, letters, and dialogues, and Seneca’s epistles to
Lucilius offer a tentative and experimental mixture of Stoicism and other
philosophical schools (many of his earlier letters end with quotations from
Epicurus, for example). In any case, Boswell, cp. 130 citing ancient sources
claiming that the very founder of stoicism, Zeno, engaged in sexual practices
with males (perhaps even exclusively) tnote that many ancient stoics actually
seem to have considered the question of sexual praticess between males to e
ETHICALLY NEUTRAL. Finally, It is worth noting that both Seneca and Cicero were
thought not to have practiced what they prached. In a discussion of how
Seneca’s behaviour often stood in contracition to his own teachings, the
historian DIO CASSIUS observes that although he married well, Seneca also “takes
pleasure in older lads, and teachers Nero do to the same thing, too”. Dio 61 10
4. Tas te aselgeias has praton gamon te epiphanestaton egme kai meikarious
exorois exaire kai tauto kai ton Nerona poietin edidaxe. The historian goes on
to insutate that Seneca fellated his partners, speculating on the reason why
refused to kiss Nero. One might imagine, Dio notes, that this was because he was gisuted by Nero’s penchant for
oral sex. But that makes no sense given Seneca’s own relations with his
boyfriends (61 10 5 o gar toi monon an
tis hupopteuseien hoti ouk ethele toiouto stoma philein elegxketai ek ton
paidikon autou pseudos on). The younger
Pliny (Epist. 7.4) informs us that Cicero addresses a love poem to his faithful
slave and companion Tiro. Of course neither of these pieces of information
tells us anything about Cicero’s or Seneca’s actual experiences. Cicero’s poem
could have been a literary game and the stories a out Seneca that constituted
Dio’s source may well have been unfounded gossip (For Cicero and Tiro, see
McDermott and Richlin. P. 223, Canatarella p. 103 assumes that they actually
ENJOYED A sexual relationship)). On the other hand, is it not impossible that
Cicero actually DID experience DESIRE for Tiro and that Seneca DID enjoy the
company of MATURE MALE SEXUAL PARTNERS. And abovre all it is important to
recognize that later generations of Romans (the younger Pliny and Dio) were
willing to IMAGINE THOSE THINGS HAPPENING. Dio’s gossipy remarks and Pliny’s
comments on Cicero remind us of the cultural
context in which a philosopher’s allusion to NATURA must be placed. ( Paolo Casini.
Keywords: naturismo, naturalismo, natura, nazione, patto sociale, la legge
naturale, l’uomo, contra natura. “antica sapienza italica” razionalismo, la
metafora della lume, illuminismo, Bruno, il patto sociale -- Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Grice e Casini” – The Swimming-Pool Library.
No comments:
Post a Comment