The history of Roman philosophy began, it may be claimed, in 155
BCE with the arrival in Roma of an Athenian embassy
composed of three eminent Greek intellectuals:
the Academic Carneades (214–129
BCE),
the Stoic Diogenes, and
the Peripatetic Critolaus.
Carneades astonished his Roman hosts with his feats of forensic prowess,
including the skill of the Sophists to be able to represent either side of an
argument with equal conviction.
Of particular note were the many young Romans
who flocked to hear his lectures, marking a decisive moment in the embrace by
the Romans of Hellenic philosophy.
Traditionally, the Romans had a deep mistrust of
the Hellenes and took to philosophy only slowly and reluctantly.
The influx of
philosophers was opposed by elements in the more traditional and conservative
Roman establishment.
Cato the Censor, for example, made an effort in the early
third century BCE to have all of the Greek philosophers banned
from Roma and prohibited from ever returning.
The campaign against the
Greeks was not supported by the majority of Romans, and philosophy became a
permanent aspect of Roman life in the centuries to follow.
The backlash
nevertheless helps to explain why the serious study and application of
traditional Greek philosophy was undertaken only from the time of Cicero and Varro in the first century BCE.
M. T. Cicero was the first truly notable Roman
philosopher and remained arguably Rome's foremost practitioner.
M. T. Cicero was also the
prime exemplar in the Roman world of the influence of Hellenism on the Romans
and the flourishing of the so-called New Academy.
The Old Academy had been
founded by Plato and lasted until the fourth century BCE.
The
Middle Academy survived throughout the third and second centuries
BCE.
The New Academy was established around 100
BCE and survived until 529 CE, when it was closed
forever by Emperor Justinian.
The New Academy was characterized by its
eclecticism in the way that it utilized Platonism, elements of Aristotle,
Stoicism, and other schools.
For Cicero, it was important to overcome the
influence of Carneades and his application of skepticism.
The solution to
skepticism, which questions the reliability of knowledge, for Cicero was the
formation of a consensus gentium, the common belief of the people, which
would permit moral and ethical certainty.
The Eclectic School exemplified by Cicero was only
one of several philosophical schools that flourished from the middle of the
first century to 225 CE, the founding date of Neoplatonism.
The chief schools of this
period were
Epicureanism, and
the Cynics.
Neo-Pythagoreanism was most represented among the
Romans by Nigidius Figulus.
While never a formally organized school, it
exercised considerable influence on the academy and on the Neoplatonists.
The Pythagoreans evidenced a traditional
fascination with numbers, but they also developed an intense interest in magic,
mysticism, and the study of the transcendence of God.
The Stoics of the Late Stoa flourished during the
first centuries of the Roman Empire and claimed three significant Roman
adherents:
Epictetus (60–117 CE), and especially Emperor
Marcus Aurelius (121–180
CE).
Influenced by Heraclitus, the "Weeping Philosopher" (ca.
544–484 BCE), the Stoics placed much stress on morality.
The
writings of Seneca demonstrate this, with their focus on the moral depravity of
Rome during the reigns of Emperors Claudius and Nero.
Likewise, Epictetus
authored a compendium on Stoic morality, the Moral Enchiridion, edited by
his student, Flavius Arrianus.
Marcus
Aurelius was also intensely concerned with Stoic morality, although his own
ethical system did not prevent him from continuing the persecution and execution
of Christians, in large measure because he saw Christianity as baneful for
society and the state.
Established as a reaction to the strict moral and
ethical system of the Stoics, the Epicureans placed pleasure as the essential
requirement of happiness, although Epicurus (341–270 BCE) argued
that he was never a selfish hedonist.
The Epicureans thus declared that while every pleasure was good on
its own account, not every pleasure has to be pursued.
Equally, they believed
that humans do not have to avoid every pain, even if every pain is evil.
Additionally, the Epicureans later developed theories pertaining both to physics
and to logic and emphasized human freedom over the Stoic tendencies toward fate.
For these reasons, Epicureanism found a wide following among the sensualist
Romans and among those who saw the importance of the innate human pursuit of
happiness.
Finally, the Cynics were never organized into
anything approaching a formal school, such as the Stoics and Epicureans, but
they nevertheless enjoyed wide public popularity in late first century
CE Rome.
The Cynics were founded upon the principles laid down by
Diogenes of Sinope (including the attainment of happiness by meeting human needs
in the easiest, most simple means possible), although many Cynics preferred
giving credit to Antisthenes.
They achieved considerable influence in the third
century BCE and then faded until a marked revival in the first
century CE. Dio Cassius noted the large numbers of Cynics in Rome
during the reign of Vespasian.
They troubled the Flavian establishment with
their calls for austerity and rejection of all social conventions and were
subsequently banished from the city by exasperated emperors.
The chief
representatives of the Cynics during this period were Demetrius the Cynic, Demonax, and Oenomaus of Gadara.
The
movement declined steadily throughout the second century CE but
remained in existence until at least the sixth century.
Suggested Readings:
Annas, Julia. Ancient Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000;
Clark, Stephen R. L. From Athens to Jerusalem: The Love of Wisdom and the Love of God. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.
Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy. Vols. 1–2. New York: Image Books, 1985.
Kaufmann, Walter, and Forrest E. Baird, eds. Philosophic Classics. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1994;
Kingsley, Peter. Ancient Philosophy, Mystery, and Magic: Empedocles and Pythagorean Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995; Walsh, Martin J. A History of Philosophy. London: G. Chapman, 1985; Wedberg, Anders. A History of Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982.
No comments:
Post a Comment