Luigi Speranza -- Grice e Casini: la
ragione conversazionale e l’implicatura conversazionale de naturismo – il
concetto di natura a Roma – scuola di Roma – filosofia romana – filosofia lazia
-- filosofia italiana – Luigi Speranza, pel Gruppo di Gioco di H. P. Grice, The
Swimming-Pool Library (Roma). Filosofo romano. Filosofo lazio. Filosofo
italiano. Roma, Lazio. Grice: “I like
Casini – he takes, unlike me, physics seriously! But then so
did Thales, according to Aristotle! – At Clifton we did a lot of ‘physical’
rather than ‘metaphysical’ education!” – Linceo. Studia a Roma sotto
Nardi, Antoni, e Chabod. Si laurea sotto Spirito (disc. Gregory) con “L'idea di
natura”. I suoi interessi di ricerca in storia della filosofia si
sono successivamente estesi all'intreccio tra filosofia e scienze sperimentali
nel Settecento, soprattutto attorno alla figura di Isaac Newton e alla
diffusione della sintesi newtoniana nella cultura filosofica europea, a
proposito di filosofi come D'Alembert, Buffon, Maupertuis, Clairaut, Eulero,
non senza tener conto dell'opera divulgativa di Voltaire, fino a collocare in
tale contesto Kant. Insegna a Trieste, Bologna, e Roma. Le sue
ricerche riguardano Diderot e la filosofia dell'illuminismo, i nessi tra
rivoluzione scientifica e riflessione filosofica, l'origine e diffusione della
fisica di Newton, le vicende del mito pitagorico tra "prisca
philosophia" e "antica sapienza italica", le dispute sorte
attorno al darwinismo. Altre opere: “Diderot "philosophe",
Laterza); Mecanicismo -- L'universo-macchina: origini della filosofia
newtoniana, Laterza); Rousseau, Laterza); Introduzione all'illuminismo,
Laterza -- razionalismo); Newton e la coscienza europea (Il Mulino); “Progresso
ed utopia” (Laterza); “L'antica sapienza italica. Cronistoria di un mito” (Il
Mulino); “Hypotheses non fingo” (Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura); “Alle
origini del Novecento: "Leonardo", rivista filosofica di Firenze (Il
Mulino); Il concetto di creazione (Il Mulino). La lista di
autorità e l’accenno alla filosofia nazionale preludono al Platone. --Paolo
Casini. Si tratta di un saggio dedicato all'evoluzione del mito
pitagorico nella cultura europea. Senza cadere mai nella rassegna erudita,
l'autore segue passo passo le trasformazioni del mito dalla sua prima
incarnazione nella cultura romana alla riscoperta operata nel Rinascimento,
alle discussioni storico-archeologiche e alle strumentalizzazioni
politiche del Sette-Ottocento. Giuseppe
Bottai o delle ambiguità (Un'erma bifronte - Leader revisionista - Nella babele
corporativa - La guerra di Pisa - «Starci con la mia testa» - Apologia –
Espiazione) - 2. Ugo Spirito: «scienza» e «incoscienza» (Una teoresi
postidealista - Teorico dell'economia corporativa - Il «bolscevico» epurato
Mutevolezza e instabilità Scienza», ricerca», «arte» - Guerra e Dopoguerra -
Alla ricerca del padre) - 3. Camillo Pellizzi: il fascio di Londra e la
sociologia (Genius loci - Tra Roma e Londra - Pax romana in Albione -
«Aristòcrate» - Dottrina del fascismo - Il postfascismo e la «rivouzione
mancata» - Verso la sociologia) - 4. I doni di Soffici («Si parla» - «Scoperte
e massacri» - Sguardi retrospettivi: tragedia e catarsi - Docta ignorantia -
«Commesso viaggiatore dell'assoluto» - Genus irritabile vatum - Un dialogo tra
sordi - Amici e nemici) - 5. Un autoritratto (A metà ventennio – Riflessi - Tra
casa e scuola - Agrari in Toscana - I primi pedagoghi - L'Istituto Massimo sj -
Vinceremo! - Il passaggio del fronte – Dopoguerra - Scuola a Firenze - Al Liceo
Tasso) - 6. Studium Urbis (Gli anni Cinquanta - Nardi e Chabod - Eredità idealistiche
- Ideologie in crisi – Diderot - Roma, gli amici - Savinio, Carocci - La naja –
Intermezzi - Olivetti, Ivrea - La "cultura" della RAI – Let Newton Be
- Anni di prova) - Indice dei nomi Order Zoogonia e
"Trasformismo" nella fisica epicurea Giornale Critico Della Filosofia
Italiana 17 (n/a). Like Recommend Bookmark L'universo-Macchina Origini Della
Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. 1969. 1 citation of this work
Like Recommend Bookmark 10 Zev Bechler, Newton's Physics and the
Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution. Boston Studies in the
Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer
(review) British Journal for the History of Science The
"Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes of ideology Rivista di Filosofia
Political Theory Like Recommend Bookmark Éléments de la philosophie de Newton
(review) British Journal for the History of Science Isaac Newton Like Recommend
Bookmark 10 Rousseau e l'esercizio della sovranità Rivista di Filosofia
Jean-Jacques Rousseau Like Recommend Bookmark 9 Il momento newtoniano in
Italia: un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 2. 2006. Like
Recommend Bookmark 5 Newton in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia Newton 1
citation of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie Arouet de
Voltaire, Éléments de la philosophie de Newton, critical edition by Robert L.
Walters and W. H. Barber. The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15.
Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, Taylor Institution, British Journal for the
History of Science 17th/18th Century French Philosophy Like Recommend Bookmark
Lo spettro del materialismo e la "Sacra famiglia" Rivista di
Filosofia Lumi e utopie in uno studio di Bronislaw Baczko Rivista di Filosofia
The New World and the Intelligent Design Rivista di Filosofia Anti-Darwinist
ApproachesDesign Arguments for Theism Like Recommend Bookmark Scienziati
italiani del Seicento e del Settecento Rivista di Filosofia Kant e la
rivoluzione newtoniana Rivista di Filosofia Kant: Philosophy of Science Like
Recommend Bookmark » Ottica, astronomia, relatività: Boscovich a Roma; «
Rivista di Filosofia Introduzione All'illuminismo da Newton a Rousseau Laterza;
Like Recommend Bookmark Newton e i suoi
biografi Rivista di Filosofia Diderot e Shaftesbury Giornale Critico Della
Filosofia Italiana L'iniziazione Pitagorica Di Vico Rivista di Storia Della
Filosofia; Like Recommend Bookmark Per
Conoscere Rousseau with Jean-Jacques Rousseau Mondadori. 1976. Jean-Jacques
Rousseau Toland e l'attività della materia Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia
British Philosophy, Misc L'eclissi della scienza' Rivista di Filosofia
Rousseau, il popolo sovrano e la Repubblica di Ginevra Studi Filosofici Il mito
pitagorico e la rivoluzione astronomica Rivista di Filosofia Newton, Leibniz e
l'analisi: la vera storia Rivista di Filosofia; Like Recommend Bookmark
13 Francesco Bianchini und die europäische gelehrte Welt um 1700 Early Science
and Medicine History of Science Like Recommend Bookmark L'antica Sapienza
Italica Cronistoria di Un Mito. 1998. Pythagoreans Like Recommend
Bookmark 16 Candide, Theodicy and the «Philosophie de l'Histoire» Rivista
di Filosofia La filosofia a Roma Rivista di Filosofia Vico's initiation into
the study of Pythagoras Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Pythagoreans Topic
Order Teoria e storia delle rivoluzioni scientifiche secondo
Thomas Kuhn Rivista di Filosofia Il
problema D'Alembert Rivista di Filosofia Semantica dell'Illuminismo Rivista di
Filosofia Cheyne e la religione naturale newtoniana Giornale Critico Della
Filosofia Italiana Newton's Physics and
the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution (review) British Journal
for the History of Science Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark 1 Diderot
and the portrait of eclectic philosophy Revue Internationale de Philosophie
Diderot Like Recommend Bookmark 6 "Magis amica veritas": Newton
e Descartes Rivista di Filosofia Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark La Natura
Isedi. 1975. Like Recommend Bookmark Voltaire, la geometria della visione e la
metafisica Rivista di Filosofia Leopardi apprendista: scienza e filosofia
Rivista di Filosofia Studi stranieri sulla filosofia dei Lumi in Italia Rivista
di Filosofia Il metodo di Foucault e le
origini della rivoluzione francese Rivista di Filosofia Rousseau e Diderot
Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Diderot « philosophe » Revue Philosophique de
la France Et de l'Etranger Continental Philosophy 1 citation of this work Like
Recommend Bookmark Newton: gli scolii classici Giornale Critico Della Filosofia
Italiana La ricerca embriologica in Italia da Malpighi a Spallanzani Rivista di
Filosofia L'empirismo e la vera
filosofia: il caso Scinà Rivista di Filosofia 8The Newtonian moment in Italy: A
post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Classical Mechanics Like
Recommend Bookmark 6 James, Freud e il determinismo della psiche Rivista
di Filosofia Freud Grean: Shaftesbury's philosophy of religion and ethics. A
study in enthusiasm (review) Studia Leibnitiana
Herschel, Whewell, Stuart Mill e l'«analogia della natura» Rivista di
Filosofia Newton: the classical scholia History of Science; 1 reference in this
work 15 citations of this work Diderot et le portrait du philosophe éclectique
Revue Internationale de Philosophie Morte e trasfigurazione del testo Rivista
di Filosofia L'universo-Macchina Origini Della Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. Bechler, Newton's Physics and the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific
Revolution. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer
(review) British Journal for the History of Science Éléments de la philosophie
de Newton (review) British Journal for the History of Science 2Isaac Newton
Like Recommend Bookmark 6 The "Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes
of ideology Rivista di Filosofia Political Theory Il momento newtoniano in
Italia: un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Rousseau e l'esercizio
della sovranità Rivista di Filosofia
Jean-Jacques Rousseau Topic Order 5 Newton
in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia saac Newton 1 citation of this work Like
Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie Arouet de Voltaire, Éléments de la
philosophie de Newton, critical edition by Robert L. Walters and W. H. Barber.
The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, Taylor
Institution, (review) British Journal
for the History of Science. 17th/18th Century French Philosophy. Grice: “An
assumption generally shared by those who wrote and read the tests surveyed in
Latin is that male desire can normally and normatively be directed at either
male of female objects. If this configuration is held to be NORMAL or
NORMATIVE, we might expect that it would also be represented as NAATURAL, and
it is thus worthwhile to consider the role played by the discourse of NATURE in
ancient representations of sexual behaviour. This question is both hughe and
complex.Important discussions include Boswell, 1Foucault, 1986, 150-7, 189-227,
and Winkler, 20-1 36-7 114 8. but one thing is clear: the ancient rhetoric of
nature, as it relates to sexual practices, displays significant differenct from
more recent discourses. Boswell, for example, observes that while “what is
supposed to have been the major contribution of Stoicism to Christian sexual
morality – the idea that the sole ‘natural’ and hence moral use of sexuality is
procreation, is in fact a common belief of amny philosophies of the day’ at the
same time, ‘the term UNNATURAL was applied eto everything from POSTNATAL CHILD
SUPPORT to legal contracts between friends (Boswell). ‘The objection that
homsosexuality is ‘unnatural’ appears, in short, to be neither scientifically
nor morally cogent and probably represents mnothing more than a derogatory
epithet of unusual emotiona impact due to a confluence of historically
sanctioned prejudiced and ill-formed ideas about ‘nature.’”Thus, as Winkler
notes, the contrast between nature and non-nature, when deployed in ancient
writings simply ‘does not posess the same valence that it does today’ Winkler,
p. 20 Moreover, nearly all of the texts that offer opinions on whether specific
secual practice is in accordance with nature are works of philosophy. The
guestion does NOT seem to have seriously engaged the writers of texts that
directly spoke to and reflected popular moral conceptions (e. g. graffiti,
comedies, epigram, love poetry, oratory). For this important distinction
between the morallyity espoused by a philosopher and what we might call popular
morality, see the introduction and chapter 1. In short, as Richinlin warns us, the question
I ‘something of a red herring, since the concept of nature takes a larger and
more ominous form in our Christian culture than it did in AAncient Rome,
whetere itw as a matter for philosophers’.Richlin, p. 533. But it may
nonetheless be worthwhile to attempt a preliminary exploration of how the
rhetoric of NATURE was applied by some ROMAN PHILOSOPHERS to sexual practices,
particularly those between males.In other words. I would like to go a step or
two beyond that ‘nature’ is generally used by Roman moralists to justify what
they approve of’ (Edwards 88 n. 87). always bearing in mind, however, that to
the extent that it was mostly taken up by philsoeophers, the question of
‘natural’ sexual practice seems not to have played a significant role in most
public discourse among Romans. Nonphilosophical texts sometimes do deploy the
rhetoric of NATURE in conjunction with sexual practices, at least insofras they
as they offer representations of ANIMAL bheaviour, one possible component in
arguments about what is natural.2-6, and Win3, on Philo’s description of
crocodiles mating. kler, 2See for example Boswell, 137-43, 15 It will come as
no surprise that Roman writers images of animals’ sexual practices are
transparetntly influenced by their own cultural traditions. Thus in no Roman
text do we find an explicit appeal to animal bhehaviour in order to condemn
sexual practices between males as unnatural.Such an argument does occasionally
appear in Greek texts, such as Plato, Laws 836c (martua parag Omenos en ton
therios phusin kai deiknos pros ta toitauta oux aptomenon arena arrenos dia to
me phusei touto einai – and Lucian Amores 36. To Be sure, Musonius Ruffus’s
condemnation of sexual practices between males as para phusin might imply a
reference to animal practices, and it is possible that in some work now lost to
us the Roman Stoic followed in Plato’s footsteps in being explicit on the
point. A Juvenalian satire does make reference to animal behaviour in orer to
condemn cannibalism (claiming that no animas eat member s of their own species
Juv. And in a passage discussed later in this appendix, Ovid has a character
argue that NO FEMALE ANIMAL experiences SEXUAL DESIRE for other females. These
claims are as unsupportable as the claim that sexual practices between males do
not occur anong nonhuman animals.This is obvious to anyone who has spent time
with dogs. With regard to the academic-study of the question, the remarks of
Wolfe, Evolution and Female Primate Sexual Behaviour, in Understanding
behaviour: what primate studies tell us about human behaviour Oxford, p.are as
illuminating as they are depressing. ‘I have taked with several (anonymous at
their request) primatologists who have told me that they have observed both
male and female homosexual bheaviour during field studies. They seemed
reluctant t publish their data, however,
either because THEY FEARED HOMOPHOBIC REEACTIONS (‘my ccolleagues might thank
that I am gay’) or because they lack a framework for analysis (‘I don’t know
what it means’). On the latter point Wolfe insightfully comments that the same
problem affects our attempts to understand ANY sexual interactions among
primates. ‘Because the alloprimates do not possess language, it is impossible
to inquir into their sexual eroticism. In other words, homosexual and
heterosexual behaviours can be observed, recorded, and analysed, but we cannot
infer either homoeroticism or heteroeroticism from such behaviours (p. 131). But
the fact that we do find animal behaviour cited by Roman authors to CONDEMN
such phenomena as cannibalism and same-sec desire among females, but not
SAME-SEX desire among males, merely proves the point. These rhetorical
strategies reveal more about ROMAN cultural concerns than about actual animal
behaviour. A poem in the Appendix Vergiliana introduces us to a lover hhappyly
separated from his beloved Lydia. In the throes of his grief he cries out that
this miserable fate NEVER BEFALLS ANIMALS: A bull is never without his cor, nor
a he-goat without his mate. In fact, sighs, the lover: ET MAS QUACUMEQUE EST
ILLA SUA FEMINA IUNCAT INTERPELLATOS SUMPAUQM PLORAVIT AMORES CUR NON ET NOBIS
FACILIS NAUTRA FUISTI CUR EGO CRUDELEM PATIOR TAM SAEPE DOLOREM? (Lydia 35-8). The
lover is melodramatically weepy and that consideration partially accounts of
his ridiculous claim that male animals are never to be seen without their
mates. Still, amatory hyperbole aside the verses nicely illustrate the tendency
to shape both natura and animal bheaviour into whatever form is convenient for
the argument at hand. Thus, Ovid,s suggesting that the best way to appease
one’s angry mistress is in bed, portrays sexual behaviour among early human
beings and animals s as the primary force that effects RECONCILIATION (Ars. The
poet offers a lovely panorama in which animal behaviour is invoked as a
POSTIIVE paradigm for specific human practices: unting otherwise scattered
groups (2. 473-80) and mollifying an angry lover (2. 481-90). Less than two
hundred lines later, the same poet invokes animalas as A NEGATIVE PARADIGM,
again in support of a characteristically human concern: discretion in sexual
matters. IN MEDIO PASSIMQUE COIT PECUS HOC QUOQUE VISO AVETIT VULTUS NEMPE
PUELLA SUOUS CONVENIUNS THALAMI FURTIS ET IANUA NOSTRIS PARSQUE SUB INJIECAT
VESTE PUDDAN LATET ET SI NON TENEBRAS AT QUIDDAM NUBIS OPACAE QUAERIMUS ATQUE
ALIQUID LUCE PATENTE MINUS (Ovid, Ars, 2 615-20). Drawing his objets lesson to
a close, Ovid holds up his own behaviour as a pattern to follow. NOS ETIAM
VEROS PARCE PROFITEMUR AMORES TECTAQUE SUNT SOLIDA MYSTIFCA FURTA FIDE. And we
are reminded of the strategies of this pasage’s broader context. If you want to
keep your girlfriend happy, do not kiss and tell: that is the argument in
service of which animal behaviour is invoked as NEGATIVE paradigm. These to
Ovidian passages illustrate the utilyt of arguments from the animal world. Just
look ant the animals and see how much we resemble them; just look at the51-5. animals and see how far we have come.An
epigram by theGreek poet Strato gives the later poin an dineresting twist. We
huam beings, he writes, are SUPERIOR to animals in that, in addition to vaginal
intercourse, we have discovered ANAL INTERCOURSE, thus men who are dominated by
women are really no better than mere animals (A P PAN ALOGON soon bivei monon oi ligkoi de ton
allon zoon tout exkomen to pleon pugizein eurotntes hosoi de guanxi kratountai
ton alogon zoon ouden exousi kleon. It all depends on the eye – and rhetorical
needs – of the beholder. OS it is that Roman writers show how Roman they are
through the picture they paint of sexual practices among animals of the same
sex. Ovid himself, in his Metamorphoses, imagines the plight of young girl
named Iphis who has fallen in love with another girl. In a torrent of self-pity
and self-abuse, she expostulates on her passion, making a simultaneous appeal
to NATURA and to the animals that is reminiscent of Ovid’s sweeping review of
animal bheaviour in the Ars amatorial just cited. But this time the paradigm is
an emphatically negative one. SI DI MIHI PARCERE VELLENT PARCERE DEBUERANT SI
NON ET PERDERE VELLENT NAUTRALE MALUM SALTEM ET DE MORE DEDISSENT NEC CACCAM
VACCA NEC EQUAS AMOR URIT EQUARUM: URIT OVES ARIES SEQUITUR SUA FEMINA CERVUM
SIC ET AVES COEUNT INTERQUE ANIMALIA UNCTA FEMINA FEMINEO ONREPTA CUPIDINE
NULLA EST (Ov. Met. 9. 728-34) As with Lydia’s lover, so here we have the
melodramatic expostulations of an unah[py lover, and similarly her view of
animal behaviour does not correspond to the realities of that behaviour. Still,
these arguments are pitched in such a way as to invite a Roman reader’s
agreement, and the sexual practices invoked as natural and occurring among the
animals demonstrate a SUSPICIOUS SIMILARTY to the sexual practices and desired
SEMMED ACCEPTABLE BY ROMAN CULTURE (the female never leaves the male,
heterosexual intercourse is a convenient and pleasurable way of unting
different social groups, and females never lust after females), or to
specifically HUMAN EROTIC STRATEGIES: we do not copulate in public, and we
should not kiss and tell if we want our to keep our partners happy. It cannot
be coincidental that, whereas Ovid invokes animal behaviour in the context of a
girl’s tortured rejection of her own passionalte yearnings for another girl,
the mythic compendium in which this natrratie is found is peppered with stories
involves passion and sexual relations between males. Both Orfeo (after losing
his wife Euridice) and the gods themselves (whether married or not) are
represented as ‘giving over their love to TENDER MALES, harvesting the BRIEF
springtime and its first flowers before maturaity sets in” Ov. Met. 10. 83-5
ORPHEUS ETIAM THRACUM POPULIS FUIT AUCTOR AMORET IN TENEROS TRANSFERRE MARES
CITRAQUE IUVENTAM AETATIS BREVE VER ET PRIMOS CARPERE FLORES. The stories that
Orfeo proceeds ts to relate include those of the young CYPARISSUS once loved by
Apollo Met 10.106-42 and the tales of Zeus and Ganumede, Apollo and Hyacinth
(Met 10 155-219 Consider also the beautiful sixteen yer old Indian boy Athis
and his Assyrian lover Lycabas (Met. A passage which echoes of Virgil’s lines
on NISUS AND EURIALO discussed in chapter 2. And the remark that the stunning
but haughty young Narcissus, also in his sixteenth year, had many admireers of
both sexses (Met. None of Ovid’s characters arever questions the NATURAL status
of that kind of erotic experience or invokes the animals in order to reject it.
Aulus Gellius preserves for us some anecdotes that further demonstrate the
manner in which animal bheaviour could be made to conform to human paradigms.
Writing of (IMPLICITLY MALE) dolfns who fell in love with beautiful boys (one
oft them even died of a broek heart after losing his beloved) Gellius exclaims
that they were acing “in amazing human ways” 606C-D and Plin N H 8 25-8 for
this and other tales of male dolphins falling in love with human boys. Gell 6 8
3 NEQUE HI AMAVERUNT QUOD SUNT IPSI GENUS SED PUEROS FORMA LIBERALI IN
NAVICULIS FORE AUT IN VADIS LITORUM CONSPECTOS MIRIS ET HUMANIS MODIS ARSERUNS.
Cf. Athen 13 Once again, the comment tells us more about ‘human ways’ than
about dolphins. The elder Plini, who alo relates this story regarding the
dolphin, introduces his encyclopeic discussion of elephants by observing that
they are nonly the largest land animals but the ones closest to human beings in
their intelligence and sense of morality. In particular, they take pleasure in
love and pride (AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS), and by way of illustration of the
‘power of love’ (AMORIS VIS) among elephants he cites two examples: ONE MALE
FELL IN LOVE WITH A FEMALE FLOWER_SELLER, another with a young Syractusan man
named MENANDER who was in Ptolemy’s army. Likehise he tells of a MALE GOOSE who
fell in love with a beautiful young Greek MAN, and of another who loved a female
musician whose beauty as such that she alstro attracted the attention of a ram.
-4. NEC QUIA DESIT ILLIS AMORIS VIS, NAMQUE TRADITUR UNUS AMASSE QUANDAM IN
AEGYPTO COROLLAS VENDENTEM ALLUS MENANDRUM SYRACUSANUM INCIPIENTIS IUVENTAE IN
EERCITU PTOLEMACI DESIDERIUM EIUS QUOTIENS NON VIDERET INEDIA TESTATUS 10.51
QUIN EST FAMA AMORS AEGII DILECTA FORMA PUERI NOMINE OLENII AMPHILOCHI, ET
GLAUCES PTOLOMAEO REGI CITHARA CANENTIS QUAM EODEM TEMPORE ET ARIES AMASSE
PRODITUR. Plin N H MAXIMUM EST EPLEPHANS PROXIMUMQUE HUMANIS SENSIBUS QUIPPE
INTELLECTUS ILLIS SERMONIS PATRII ET IMPERIORUM OBEDIENTIA, OFFICIOURM QUAE
DIDICERE MEMORIA, AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS 8 13Turing to the concept of
NATURA as it applied to sexual pracyices by ancient writers, we being with
basica basic problem. The very term NATURA has various referents in those
texts. Sometimes NATURA seems simply to refer to the way things are or to the
INHERENT nature OF something, sometimes to the way things SHOULD be according
to the intention ordictates of some transcendent imperative. Thus Foucault
speaks of ‘the ‘three axes of nature’ in philosophical discourse. The general
order of the world, the orgginal state of mankind, and a behaviour that is
reasonably adapted to natural ends.Fouctault, p. 215-6. See also the
discussions in Boswell, p. 11-5, where he distinguishes between ‘realistic’ and
‘ideal’ notions of nature, Beagon, and Levy, “Le concept de nature a Rome: la
physique, Paris). The first two of these axes are evident in a wife-variety of
Roman texts. Departures from what is observably the usual PHYSICAL constitution
of various thbeings could be called NONNATURAL or UNNATURAL even by
nonphilosophical authors. The Minotuar, centaurs, a snake with feet, a bird
with four wings, and a sexual union between a woman (the muthis Pasiphae) and a
bull.snAnon De Differentiis 520 23 MONSTRUM EST CONTRA NATURAM UT EST
MINOTAURUS. Serv. Aen 6. 286 (centaurs) Suet Prata fr. 176.113-5 snakes with feet, birds with four wings.
Serv. Aen. 1. 235.11. Pasiphae and the bull. Te elder Plinty claims that breech
births are ‘against nature’ since it is ‘nature’s way’ that we should be born
head first.n N H 7 45 -6. IN PEDES PROCIDERE NASCENTEM CONTRA NATURAM EST RITUS
NATURAE CAPITE HOMINEM GIGNI MOST EST PEDIBUS EFFERRI. PLiQuintilian argues
that to push one’s hair back from the forehead in order to achieve some
dramatic effect is to act ‘against nature’.Quint I O 11 3 160 CAPILLOS A FRONTE
CONTRA NATURAM RETRO AGERE. and Seneca himself opines that being carried about
in a litter is ‘contra natural’a, since nature has gives us feet and we should
use them.Sen. Epist 55 ` LABOR EST ENIM ET DIU FERI AC NESCIO AN EO MAIOR QUIA
CONTRA NATURAM EST QUAE PEDES DEDIT UT PER NOS AMBULAREMUS. Finally, the belief
that physical disabilities and disease are UNNAUTARAL, and thus, implicitly,
that a healthy body displaying no marked derivations from the form illustrates
what nature designed or intended, surfaces in a number of texts, arnign from Celusus’
mdical treatise to Ciceroo’s philosophical works to declamations attributed to
Quintilian, to a moral epistle fo Seneca to the, to the Digest.2 1. 60 pr. MOTUS CORPORIS CONTRA NATURAM QUAM FEBREM APPELLANT. Quint. Decld. Min. 298.12 WEAK AND MALFORMED BODIES ARE IMPLICITLY CCONTRA NATURAM.
Celsus Medic 3 21 15. On fluids that are retained in the body contra naturam.
Cic Off 3 30 MORBUS EST CONTRA NATURAM. Gell. Labeo defines morbus asHABITUS
CUIUSQUE CORPORIS CONTRA NATURAM QUI USUUM ETIUS FACIT DETERIOREM. Cf. D. 21 1
1 7. D. 4Along the same lines, some ancient writers also suggest that to harm a
healthy body with poisons and the like is unnatural.Quint Decl. Min. 246.3 the
plaintiff refers to a substance as a venenum QUONIAM MEDICAMENTUM SIT ET
EFFICIAT ALIQUID CONTRA NATURAM. Sen Epist 5. 4. To torment one’s body and to
eat unhealthy food is CONTRA NATURAM. As for the third of the axes described by
Foucault, anthropologists and others have long observed that proclamations
concerning practices that are in acoordance with nature often turn out to
reflect specific cultural traditions. As Winkler puts it, for nature we may
often read culture.Winkler p. 17. In the same way Edwards p. 87-8 discusses a
passage from Seneca (Epist.) discussed in chapter 5, having to do with women
who violate their ‘nature.’ She concludes that ‘Seneca was not reacting to
naturally anomalous bheaviour. He was taking part in the reproduction of a a
cultural system.’ So too Veyne, p. 26. ‘When an ancient says that something is
unnatural, he does not mean that it is disgraceful (monstrueuse) that that it
does not conform with the rules of society, or that it is perverted OR
ARTIFICIAL”. Roman sources of various types certainly support that contention.
Thus, for example, violations of traditional PRINCIPLELS OF LANGUAGE AND
RHETORIC which are surely among the most intensely cutlrual of human phenomeno
are SOMETIMES SAID TO BE UNNATURAL.Serv. Comm. Art Don. PLINIUS AUTEM DICIT BARBARISMUM ESSE SERMOVEM
UNUM IN QUO VIS SUA EST CONTRA NATURAM – Serv Aen. 4. 427. REVELLI NON REVULSI.
NAM VELLI ET REVELLI DICIMUS. VULSUS VERO ET REVULSUS
USURPATUM EST TANTUM IN PARTICIPIIS CONTRA NATURAM cf. Sen. Contr. 10, pr. 9 – tof the rhetorician Musa. OMNIA USQUE AD ULTIMUM TUMOREM
PERDUCTA UT NON EXTRA SANITATEM SED EXTRA NATURAM ESSENT. One legal writer
invokes the rhetoric of NATURA to justify the principle of individual ownership
(joint possession of a single object is said to be CONTRA NATURAL.D. 41 2 3 5
CONTRA NATURAM QUIPPE EST UT CUM EGO ALIQUID TENEAM TU QUOTE ID TENERE
VIDEARIS. Interestingly, another jurist argues that the principle underlying
the institution of slavery – that one person can be owned by another – is
actually ‘unnatural’ (D. SERVITUS EST CONSTITUTIO IURIS GENTIUM QUA QUIS
DOMINIO ALIENO CONTRA NATURAM SUBICITUR. In a Horatioan satire we read that
NATURA sees it that no one is every truly the ‘master’ of the land that he
legally owns, and Natura puts a limit on how much one can inherit (Hor. Sat.). Sallust
describes the violation of the cultural and more specifically philosophical
tradition priviliengy the SOUL over the BODY as UNNATRUAL.Sall. Cat. QUIVUS
PROFECT CONTRA NATURAM CORPUS VOLUPTATI, ANIMA OVERI FUIT. SALLUST. Likewise,
practices violating Roan ideologies of MASCULINITY are represented as INFRACTIONS
NOT of cultural tranditions s but of the natural order. Cicero’s philosophical
tratise DE FINIBUS includes a discussion of the parts and with some clarity
functions of the BODY that illustrates the relation between NATURE and
MSASCULINITY with some clarity Our bodily parts, Cicero argues, are PERFECTLY
DESIGNED to fulfil their functions, and in doing so they are in conformance
with nature. But there are certain bodily movesmesns NOT in accord with nature
(NATURAE CONGRUENTES> If a man were to walk on his hand or to walk
backwyasds, he would manifestbly be rejecgting his identity as a human and
thuswould thus be displayeing a ‘hattred of nature’ (NAUTRAM ODISSE). Cic Fin 5
35. CORPORIS IGITUR NOSTRI PARTES TOTAQUE FIGURA ET FORMA ET STATURA QUAM APTA
AD NATURAM SIT APPARET. The claim that walking on one’s hand is unnatural
nicely illustrates the gap between ancient and more recent uses of the rhetoric
of nature – cfr. Dodgson). The next illustration Cicer o offers of bodily
moveents not in accord with natura concerns correctly masculine ways of
deporing oneself. QUAMOBREM ETIAM SESSIONES QUAEDAM ET FLEXI FRACTIQUE MOTUS,
QQUALES PROTERVORUM HOMINUM AUT MOLLIUM ESSE SOLENT, CONTRA NATURAM SUNT, UT
ETIAMSI ANIMI VITIO ID EVENIANT TAMEN IN CORPOMUTRAR MUTARI HOMINIS NATURA
VIDEATUR ITAQUE A CONTRARIO MODERATI AEQUABILESQUE HABITUS AFFECTIONS USUSQUE
CORPORIS APTI ESSE AD NAUTRAM VIDENTUR (Cic. Fin Deemed ‘agaist natture’ are
certain ways of carrying oneself that are ‘wanton’ and ‘soft,’ movements lthat,
like walking on one’s hand or stepping backwards, clasi the with thvident
purporse of the body’s various parts. Implicitly then, nature wills men’s
bodies to move and to function in certain ways. Men who violate these
principles of masculine comportment are acting BOTH EFFEMINATELY (as we saw in
chapter 4, militia is a standard metaphor for effeminacy) AND UNNATURALLLY.
Cultural traditions regarding masculinity – here, appropriate bodily gestures –
are identified with the natural order.Similar conddemnations of inappropriate
bodily comportment, marked as EFFEMINATE, abound: walking daintily, scratching
the hair delicately wih onefinger, and so on (see chapter 4 in general and see
Gleason for a general discussion of physiognomy and masculinity in antiquity. How,
then is the rheotirc of nature applied to same-sex practices? One scholar has
recently suggested that the elder Pliny describes men’s desires to be anally
penetrated as occurring ‘by crime against nature’ Taylor, p. 325. But that is
probably a misinterpretation of Pliny’s language. IN HOMINUM GENERE MARIBUS
DEVERTICULA VENERIS EXCOGIGATA OMNIA, SCLERE (or CCCELERE naturae FEMINIS VERO
AOBRTUS Plin N H. The phrase DEVERTICULA VENERIS which one might translate
(by-ways of sex’ or ‘sexual deviations’ is vague. There is no reason to think
that it refers to specifically, let alone exclusively, to the practice of being
anally penetrated. Moreover, the phrase SCELERA NATURA or SCELERE NATURAE,
rather than ‘crime against nature,’ is most obviously transated as ‘crime OF
NATURE,’ that is, a crime perpetrated BY NATURE.This is indeed the way Plinio
uses the phrase elsewhere, noting that we ought to call earthquakes ‘moracles
of the eart rather than crimes of nature’ (NH 2 206 – UT TERRAE MIRACULA POTIUS
DICAMU QUAM SCLEREA NATURAE. See Beagon. In other words (pace Taylor and
Rackham Loeb Classical Library translation, I take the genitive NATURAE to be
subjective rather than objective. I have not found any parallels for such an
objective use of a genitive noun dependent upon scelus. In any case, Pliny is
not implying that all sexual desires or practices between males are unnatural:
in this same treatise, significantly called the HISTORIA NAUTRALIS or Natural
Investigations’ he reports the story of a male elephant who fell passionately
in love with a young man from Syractuse as an illustration of the obviously
natural power of love of love (amoris vis) among elephants; likewise, he
reports the story of a gosse who loved a beautiful young man.Plin N H 8 13-4,
10.51More explicitly referring to those men who take pleasure in being
penetrated, the speaker in Juvenal’s second satire riducules menwho have
wilfully abandoned their claim on masculine status by weaking makeup,
participating in women’s religious festivals, and even taking husbands, and
notes with gratitude, that nature does not allow them gto give birth.Juv. 2 139
40. SED MELIUS QUOD NIL ANIMIS IN CORPORI IURIS NATURA INDULGET STERILES
MORTUNTUR. For Further discussion see Appendix 2. The orator Labienus decries
wealthy men who castrate their male prostitutes (EXOLETI, see chapter 2) in
order to render them more suitable for playing the receptice role in
intercourse. These men use their rinces in UNNATURAL WAYS (contra natural), and
the natural standard they they violate is apparently the principle that mature
males both should make use of the PENISES and should be IMPENETRABLE.Sen Contr.
PRINCIPES VIRI CONTRA NATURAM DIVITIAS SUAS EXERCENT CASTRATORUM GREGES HABENT
EXOLETOS SUOS AD LONGIOREM PATIENTIALM IMPUDICITIAE IDONEI SINT AMPUTANT. Firmicus
Maternus refers to men’s desires to be penetrated as CONTRA NATURAL (5. 2. 11),
and Caelius Aurelianus’s medical wirtings also reveal the assumption that men’s
‘natural’ sexual function is TO PENETRATE and not to be penetrated. NATURALIA
VENERIS OFFICIA. Cael. Aurel. Morb. Chron. 4 In short, nature’s ditactes
conveniently accorded with cultural traditions, such as those discouraging men
from seeking to be penetrated, or those deterring them from engaging in sexual
relations with other men’s wives: in a poem that urges on its male readers the
principle that NATURA places a limit of their desires, Horace remocommends, as
implicitly being in line with the requirement of nature, that men avoid
potentially dangerous affaris with married women and stick to their own slaves,
bh male and female.Hor. Sat.. NONNE CUPIDINIBUS STATUAT NATURA MODUM QUEM … Se
chapter 1 for further discussion of this poem. Cf. Sat. 1. 4.
113-4: NE SEQUERER MOECHAS CONCESSA CUM VENERE UTI POSEEM. In one of his Episles Seneca provides a lengthy and revealing discussion
of ‘unnatural’ behavours that include a reference to sexual practices among
males. He beings, however, by despairing of ‘those who have perverted the roles
of daytime and nightime, not opening their eyes, weighed down by the preceding
day’s hangover, until night begins its approach. Sen Epist 122 2 SUNT QUI
OFFICIA LUCIS NOTISQUE PERVERTERINT NEC ANTE DIDUCANT OCULOS HESTERNA GRAVES
CRAPULA QUAM ADPETERE NOX COEPIT. These people are objectionably not simply
because of their overindulgence in goof and drink but because they do not
respect the proper function of night and day.Comparing them to the Antipodes,
mythincal beings who live n the opposite side of the globe, he asks. Do you
think these people know HOW to live when they don’t even know WHEN to live?
122.3 HOS TU EXISTIMAS SCIRE QUEMADMODUM VIVENDUM SIT QUI NESCIUNT QUANDO?and
this pervesion of night and say, is, in the end, ‘unnatural’. INTERROGAS
QUOMODO HAEC ANIMAO PRAVITAS FIAT AVERSANDI DIEM ET TOTAM VITAM IN NOCTEM
TRANSFERENDI? OMNIA VITA CONTRA NAUTRAM PUGNANT, OMNIA DEBITUM ORDINEM DESERUNT
(Sen Epist.). He then proceeds to tick off a serioes of bheaviour
that are similarly CONTRA NATURAM. First, people who drink on an empty stomach
‘live contrary to nature’ Sen. 122 6 NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA NATURAM VIVERE
QUI IEIUNI BIBUNT QUI VINUM RECIPIUNT INANIBUS VENIS ET AD CIBUM EBRII
TRANSEUNT. Young men nowadsays, Seneca continues, go to the baths before a meal
and work up a sewat by drinking heavily; according to them, only hopelessly
philistine hicks (patres familiae rustici … et verae volupatigs ignari) save
their drinking for after the meal.Sen Epist 122 6. ATQUI FREQUENS HOC
ADULESCENTIUM VITIUM EST QUI VIRES EXCOLUNT UT IN IPSO PAENE BALINEI LIMINE
INTER NUDOS BIBANT IMMO POTENT ET SUDOREM QUEM MOVERUNT POTIONIBUS CREBRIS AC
FERVENTIBUS SUBINDE DESTRINGAT POST PRANDIUM AUT CENAM BIBERE VULGARE ETS HOC
PATRIS FAMILIAE RUSTICI FACIUT ET VERA VOLUPTATIS IGNARI. The latter comment,
with its contrast between URBAN AND RUSTIC life, austerity and luxyry, is a
valuable reminder of us. The standard violated by those who drank betweofre
eating was what we would call a cultural norm. But for Seneca they were
violating the dicates of NATURE, abandoning the proper order (debitum ordinem)
of things. This important point bust be borne in mind as we turn to the next
practices that come under Seneca’s fire: NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA NATURAM
VIVERE QUI OMMUTANT CUM FEMINIS VESTEM? NON VIVUNT CONTRA NAUTRA QUI
SPECTANT UT PUERITIA SPENDEAT TEMPORE ALIENO? QUID FIERI CRUDELIS VEL VISERIOUS
POTEST? NUMQUAM VIR ERIT, UT DIU VIRUM PATI POSSIT? ET CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE
SEXUS ERIPUISSE DEBUERANT NON NE AETAS QUIDEM ERIPIET (Sen. Epist.). The concept of the proper order is very much in evidence here, and here
again the order shows unmistakable signs of cultural influence. Just as those
who turn night into day or drink wine before they eat a meal are engaging in
unnatural activities, so men who wear women’s clothes live contrary to nature –
yet what could be more cultural than the designation of certain kinds of
clothing as appropriate only for men and others as appropriate only for women?
Moving on to his next point, Senceca continues to focus on extermal appearance.
Men who attempt to give the appearance of the boyhood that is in fact no longer
theirs also ‘live contrary to nature’. Again the order of things has been
disrputed. Boys should be boys, men should be men. But these particular men
want to LOOK like boys in order to find older male sexual partners to penetrate
them. Such is the thenor of Seneca’s decorous but blunt phrase, ‘so that he may
submit to a man for a long time’ (ut diu virum pati possit’). If we filter out
Seneca’s moralizing overlay, this detail gives us a fascinating fglimpse oat
Roman realities. These MEN scorned by Seneca acted upon the awareness that MEN
would be more likely to find them desirable if their bodies seemed like those
of BOYS (not men): young, smooth, irless. Moreover, the very fact that these
men made the effort suggests that th actual age of the beautiful ‘boys’ we
always hear of may not have mattered to their loveers so much as their youthful
APPEARANCE.Cf. Boswell, p. 29, 81. All of this is very much a matter of
CONVENTION, of CULtURAL traditions concerning the ‘proper order’ of things, but
Seneca insistently pays homage to NATURA.Cf. Winkler, p. 21. “Contrary to
nature means to Senea not ‘outside the order of the kosmos’ but ‘unwilling to
conform to the simplicity of the unadorned life’ and, in the case of sex,
‘going AWOL rom one’s assigned place in the social hierarchy. The importance of
this order is especially clear in the climactic illustrations of those who live
‘contrary to nature’. These are people who wish to see see roses in winter and
employ artificial means to grow lilies in the cold season; who grow orchards at
the tops of towers and trees under the roofs of their homes (this latter
proving Seneca to a veritable outburst ofm moral indignation)., and those who
construct their bathhouses over the waters of the sea Sen. Epist 122 21 NON
VIVUNT CONTRA NATURAM QUI FUNDAMENTA THERMARUM IN MARI IACIUNT ET DELICATE
NATARE IPSI SIBI NON VIDENTUR NISI CALENTIA STAGNA FLUCT AC TEMPESTATE
FERIANTUR. Finally Seneca returns to the
example of unnatural practices that sparked the whole discussion: those who
pervert the function of night and day aengage in the ultimate form of unnatural
behaviour (Sen Epist 122 9 CUM INSTITUERUNT OMNIA CONTRA NATURAE CONSUETUDINEM
VELLE NOVISSIME IN TOTUM AB ILLA DESCISCUNT LUCET SOMNI TEMPUS EST QUIES EST
NUNC EXERCEAMUR NUNC GESTEMUR NUNC PRANDEAMUS. That the practice ofs of growing
trees indoors, of building bathhouses over the sea, and of sleeping by day and
partying by night should be considered unnatural makes some sense in relation
to notions of the ‘proper order’ of things. Plants should e outdoors, buldings
should be on dray land, and people should sleep at night. But that thes
practices should be cited as the most egregious examples of unnatural bheaviour
– they constitute the climax of Seneca’s argument – demontrastes just how wide
the gap is between ancient moralists and their modern counterparts on the
question of what is natural. With regard to mature men who seek to be
penetrated by men, the third of Seneca’s examples of unnatural behaviour,
Seneca makes in passing a surprising remark. CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE SEXUS ERIPUISSE DEBUERAT NON NE AETAS QUIDEM ERIPIET?
122.7. The clear implication is that a nature man
certainly ought to be safe from ‘indignity’ (here a moralizing euphemism for
penetration), but ultimately the very fact that he is MALE, REGARDLESS OF HIS
AGE, ought to protect him. With with one pointed sentence, then, Seneca is
suggesting that MALENESS IN ITSELF IS IDEALLY INCOMPATIBLE WITH BEING
PENETRATED, and since sexual acts were almost without exception conceptualized
as REQUIRING penetration, this amounts to positing the exclusion of sexual practices
BETWEEN MALES from the ‘proper order’. This is a fairly radical suggestion FOR
A ROAM MAN TO MAKE, and Seneca was no doubt aware of that fact. He slips the
comment quietly into his discussion, makes the point rather subtly (it makight
ake a second reading even to REALISE IT IS THERE), and then instantly moves on
to other, less controversial arguments. FOR as opposed to Seneca’s suggestion
that EVERY MALE, even a boy, should somehow be ‘rescued’ from ‘indignity,’ the
usual Roman system of protocols governing men’s sexual behaviour required the
understanding that A BOY is different from A MAN precisely because they COULD
BE penetrated without necessarily forfeiting EVERY CLAIM to masculine or male
status (see especially chapter 5 on this last point). But Seneca, waxing Stoic,
here voices a dissenting opinion, as does the first century A. D. Stoic
philosopher MUSONIUS RUFUS, in one of twhose treatises we find the remark that
sexual practices BETWEEN MALES are ‘against nature’ (‘para-physical’) Muson,
Ruf. 86. 10 Lutz para phusin. The remark needs to be be put in the context of
Musonius’s philosophy of nature. According to Musonious, every createure has its own TELOS beyond the goal
of simply being aalive En a horse would not b e fully living up to its telos if
all it did was to eat, drink, and copulate (106.25-7 Lutz)., while the TELOS or
goal of a human being is to live the life or arete or VIRTUS. Thus, “each one’s
nature (phusis) leads him to his particular virtuous quality (arete), so that
it is is a reasonable conclusion that a human being is living in accordance
WITH nature NOT when he lives in pleasure, but rather when he lives in virtue” 108.1-3
Lutz). Elsewhere he opines that human nature (phusis – anthropine phusis,
natura humana, Hume, Human Nature) is not aimed at pleasure (hedone, 106.21.3
Lutz). Consequently, luxury (truphe) is to be avoided in EVERY way, as being
the cause of INJUSTICE (126.30-1 Lutz). By implication, then, eating, drinking,
and aopulating are not in themselves evil, but they can easily become sgns of a
life of luxury, and if those activities aconstitute the goals of our existence,
we are FAILING TO FULFIL OUR POTENTIAL AS A HUMAN BEING, namely, the practice
of virtue, or reason, and consequently, not living IN ACCORDANCE WITH NATURE,
but against her (paa phusin). Thus, as part of a regime of SELF-CONTROL
(MALENESS OR MASCULINITY AS SELF-CONTROL, not addictive behaviour or weakness
of the will) Musonius argues that a man should engage in a sexual practice only
within the context of marriage for the purpose of begetting children. Any other
sexual relation, even within marriage should be avoided. T”Those who do not
live licentiously, or who are not evil, must think that only those sexual
practices are justified which are consummated within marriage and for the
creation of children, since these pratcttices are licit (NOMIMA). But such
people must think that those sexual practices which hunt for mere pleasure are
unjust and illicit, even if they take place within marriage. Of Other forms of
intercourse, those committed in moikheia (I e. a sexual relation with a
freeborn woman under another man;s control) are the most illicit. No more
moderate than this is the INTERCOURSE OF MALES WITH MALES, since it is a DARING
ACT CONTRARY TO NATURE. As for those forms of intercourse with with females
apart from moikheia which are not licit (kaTa nomon) all of these are too
shameful, because done on account of a lack of self-control. If one utside to behave temperately (TEMPERANTIA,
CONTINENTIA) one would not dare to have relations with a courtesan, nor with a
free woman outside of marriage, nor, by Zeus, with one’s own slave woman
(Musonius Rufus, 86.4-14 Lutz). As I argued in chapter 1, Musonius’s final
remark reveals the extent to which the sexual morality that he is preaching is
at odds with mainstream Roman traditions. Nor is his suggestion that men should
keep their hans off prostitutes and their own slaves the only surprising
statement to be found in the treatises attributed to Musonius. He elsewhere
aargues against the obviously widespread practices of giving up for adoption or
even exposing unwanted children (Lutz), of EATING MEANT (here he explicitly
contrasts himself with the many hoi polloi who live to eat rather than the
other way around (Lutz) or SHAVING THE BEARD (128.4-6 Lutz), of using wet
nurses (42.5-9 Lutz), and most appositely, of allowing husbands sexual freedoms
not granted to wives (Lutz). Thus his condemnation of sexual practices between
MALES is issued in the context of a condemnation of ALL SEXUAL PRATICES other
than those between husband and wife aimed at procreation (strictly speaking,
vaginal intercourse when the wife is ovulating) and also in the context of a a
suspicion of all luxury oand of pleasures beyond those relating to the bare
necessities of life. Thus he condemns sexual relations between males as
contrary to nature (the implication being that the two sexes ARE DESIGNED TO
UNITE WICH EACH OTHER IN THE CONTEXT OF MARRIAGE), while sexual relations
between malesand female outside of marriage are criticized as ‘illicit
(para-noma) and as signs of lack of self-control. Here Musonius is obviously
manipulating the ancient contrast between law or convention (nomos) and nature
(phusis) and interprestingly procreative relations within marriage are
ultimately given his seal of approval not because they are more ‘natural’ than
tother sexual practices, but because they are ‘licit’ or ‘conventional’
(nomima), just as adulterious relations are most ‘illicit’ of unconventional
(paranomotatai). In other words, Musonius invokes the rhetoric of nature only
by way of secondary support.. A male-male relation is no more ‘moderate’ than a
adulterious relationa dn anyway, he adds, they are ‘unnatural’. But a relation
between a man and another man’s wife, while implicitly ‘natural’,is in the end
more ‘illicit’ than a male-male relation. Even for the Stoic Musonious, NATURA
may NOT be the ultimate arbiter. Interestingly, when he describes sexual
practices between males as being against nature, Musonius does not appeal to
animal bheaviour as does Plato in his Laws (836c). Indeed, such an argument
sould have ill-suited Musonius’s argument elsewhere that humans are different
from other animals and should not takem them as a MODEL FOR BHEAVIOUR. Thus he argues
that wise men ill not attack in return if attacked – such revenge is the
province of MERE ANIMALS – Lutz) – and that, while among animals an act of
copulation suffices to procude offspring, human beings should aim for the
lifelong union that is marriage (88.16-17 Lutz). Finally, there is an important
distinction to observe between Musonius’s remark concerning sexual practices
between males and later Christian fulminations against ‘the unnatural vice’
which came to be a code term for ‘sodomy’. On the one hand, Musonius did not go
so far as to condemn such relations as THE unnatural vice. Indeed, if we think
about the implications of his words, relations between MALES do not even
constitute the ULTIAMTE sexual crime. He declare that ADULTEROUS relations are
‘the most illicit of all’ (paranomotatai) and thus clearly more ‘illicit’ than
relations between males which are howevery ‘equally immoderate’. Furthermore
Musonius’s approach to the problem of sexual behaviour differs from later
Christian moralists in a fundamental respect. As Foucault puts it, according to
Musonius, ‘to withdraw pleasure from this form (sc. Of marriage, to detach
pleasure from the conjugal relation in order to propoeseother ends for it, is
in fact to debase the ESSENTIAL composition of the human being. The defilement
is not in the sexual act itself, but in the ‘debauchery’ that would dissociate
it from marriage, where it has its natural form and its rational purpose” Foucault
CICERONE (vedasi) ro in a passage from one of this major philosophical works,
the Tusculan disputations, approaches the ascetic stance advocated by Seneca
and Musonius Rufus, although he nowhere makes an explicit commitment to the
extreme suggested by Seneca and preached by Musonius. Speaking in the Tusculan
Disputations of the detrimental effects of erotic passion, Cicero observes that
the works of Greek poets are filled with images of love. Focusing on those who
describe LOVE FOR BOYS (he mentions Alcaeus, Anacreon, and Ibycus), Cicero
notes thain an aside that ‘NATURE HAS GRANTED A GREATER PERMISSIVENESS (maiorem
liicnetial)” to men’s affairs with women. Cic. Tusc. 4. 71. ATQUE UT MULIEBRIS
AMORES OMITTAM QUIVUS MAIOREM LICENTIAL NATURA CONCESSIT QUIS AUT DE GANYMEDI
RAPTU DUBITAT QUID POETAE VELINT AUT NON INTELLEGIT QUID APUD EURIPIDEM ET
LOQUATUR ET CUPIAT LAIUS. The comparative (MAIOREM LICENTIAL is noteworthy.
NATURE has granted ‘greater’, not exclusive license to affais with women than
to affairs with BOYS. The Latter are evidently NOT FORBIDDEN BY NATURE.
Discouraged perhaps, but not outlawed. This is a BEGRUDGING ADMISSION, in
perfect agreement with the tenor of the whole discussion of sexual passion
which had opened thus. ET UT TURPES SUNT QUI ECFERUNT SE LAETITIA TUM CUM
FRUUNTUR VENERIIS VOLUPTATIBUS SIC FLAGITIOSI QUI EAS INFLAMAMATO ANIMO
CONCPISCUNT TOTUS VERO ISTE QUI VOLGO APPELATUR AMOR – NEC HERCULE INVNEIO QUO
NOMINE ALIO POSSIT APPELARI TANTAE
LEVITATIS EST UT NIHIL VIDEAM QUOD PUTEM CONFERENDUM. (Cic. Tusc. 4. 68). These
words disparage sexual passion as a whole – particularly a hot, inflamed desire
(QUI EAST INFLAMMATO ANIMO CONCUSPICUNT) whether indulged in with women or with
boys. NATURA, according to Cicero, makes it easier to indulge in this passion
with women, so that when men DO INDULGE
IN IT WITH BOYS, they show just who DEEPLY THEY HAVE FALLEN VICTIM TO LOVE –
that treacherous and destructive power, ‘te originator of disgraveful behaviour
and inconstanty (FLAGITTI ET LEVITATIS AUCTOREM (4. 68), as G. Williams notes. In
fact, remarkably enough, Cicero later claims that love itself is not natural.
Cic. Tusc. 4 76. If love were natural, everyone would love, they would always
love, and would love the same thing: one person would not be deterred from
loving by a sense of shame, another by rational thought, another by his satiety
– ETENIM SI NAUTRALIS AMOR ESSET ET AMARENT OMNES ET SEMPER AMARENT ET IDEM
AMARENT NEQUE ALIUM PUDOR ALIUM COGITATIO ALIUM SATIETAS DETERRERET. Cicero’s
remark on NATURA and sexual relations with women is in fact fact little more
than a a passing comment. Still, its implications deserve some consideration.
In what whays does NATURE grant ‘greater permisiveness’ to a relation with aa
woma than with a boy? Why does Seneca suggest that men’s MALENESS ought to
preclude them from being PENETRATED, and why does Musonius Rufus condemn ALL
SEXUAL PRACTICES BETWEEN MALES as unnatural? These philosophers’ comments seem
to rest on certain assumptions about the function of sexual organs. Certainly
Seneca emphasixes the notion of the proper order or debitus ordon, according to
which men should not drink wine before eating, grow roses in the winter, build
buildings over the sea, or PENETRATE MALES. In short, some kind of ARGUMENT
FROM DESIGN seems to lruk in the backgrounf of Cicero’s Seneca’s and Musoniu’s
claism. The penis is ‘designed’ to PENETRATE a vagina. TA vagina is deigned to
be penetrated by a penis. Similarly the passage from Phaedrus Fables implies,
whitout actually using the word NATURA, that males who desire to be penetrated
(molles mares) and females who desire to penetrate (tribades) have A FLAWED
DESIGN. When Prometheus was assuming these people’s bodies from CLAY, he
attached the genial organs of the opposite sex in a drunken slip-up. But his
more popularizing account only specifies that those males who DESIRE to be
penetrated are anomalous. It does not designate those men who seek to penetrate
other males as unnatural. On this model, a sexual act in which a master
penetrated his UNWILLING MALE slave is
NOT UNNATURAL. By contrast, according the philosophers discussed here (Musonius
most expliclty) this act would be unnatural. But on the whole very few Roman writers seem
to have taken this kind of argument to heart. In general, ROMAN MEN’S
BEHAVIOURAL codes reflect an AWARENESS that the PENIS IS SUITED for purposes
OTHER than penetrating avagina, and that the vagina is NOT the only organ
suited for being penetrated. Such is the implication of a witty comment in an
epigram of Martial’s addressed to a man who, instead of doing the USUAL WITHIN
with his BOY and analyy penetrating him, has been STIMULATING THIS GENITALS.
This is objectionable because it will speed up the process of his maturation
and thus hasten THE ADVENT OF HIS BEARD (11.22.1-8). Martial tries to talk some
sense into his friend and the epigram ends with an APPEAL TO NATURE. DIVISIT
NATURA MAREM PARS UNA PUELLIS UNA VIRIS GENITA EST UTERE PARTE TUA Mart. The comment is of course a witticigm. Note the logical contradiction
that this playful invocation of nature creates. If the penis is designed by
nature for girls and the anus for mmen,how can a man use a boy’s anus in the
way nature intended (i. e. to be penetrated by men) and at the same time use
his own penis in the way nature intended (i. e. by penetrating a girl? See
chapters 1 and 5 for further fsucssion of this epigram together with Martial’s
humorous invocation of the paradigm of nature with regard to masturbation. but
if the humour was to succeed, the notion that a boy’s anus is designed by
nature for a man to penetrate cannot have seemed outrageous to Martial’s
readership. After all, the rhetorical goal of the epigram is to steer tha man
onto the path of right behaviour, the path which Martial’s won persona,
dutifully, even proudly, followed. This sort of comment – rather than the
passing remarks of such philosophers as Cicero, Seneca and Musonius Rufus,
reflects the mainstreat Roman understanding of what constitutes NORMATIVE and NATURAL
sexual beavhiour for a boy and for a man. It is significant, moreover, that
neither CCicero nor Seneca nor Musonius Rufus nor any other survinving Roman
text, philosophical or not, argues that a MAN’s *DESIRE* to penetrate a boy is
‘contrary to nature’. Musonius, for one, speaks ony of the sexual act
(SUMPLOKAI). We return to the Epicurean perspective offered by Lucretius cited
in chapter i. SIC IGITUR VENERIS QUI TELIS ACCIPIT ICTUS SIVE PUER MEMBRIS
MULIEBRIBUS HUNC IACULATUR SEU MULIEUR TOTO IACTANS E CORPORE AMOREM UNDE
FERITUR EO TENDIT GESTITQUE COIR ET IACERE UMOREM IN CORPUS DE CORPRE DUCTUM.
Lucr. 4. 1052-6. This are lines from a poem dedicated to teaching its Roman
readers about ‘the nature of things’ (de rerum natura 1.25). cf. Boswell p. 149
“Lucretius’s De rerum natura dealt with the whole of ‘natura’ but it was the
‘rerum’ of things – which suggested to Latin readers what modern speakers mean
by ‘nature’”. Obviously the SUSCEPTIBILITY OF MEN to THE ALLURE of boys and
women is a PART OF THE NATURAL ORDER for Lucretius. The beams of atomic
particles that EMANATE from the bodies of boys and women and attract men to
them are an integral part of the nature of things. It is the mentalitly evident
in such diverse textsa Lucretius’s poetic treatise On the nature of Things,
Martial’s epigrams, and graffiti scrawled on ancient walls that we need to keep
in mind when we evaluate the comments of Musonius Rufus, Seneca, and Cicero.
These are the words of three philosophers. Cicero expounding on the danger s of
love, Senceca inveighing against the corrputions of the world around him, and
Musonius arguing that men should engage only in certain kind of sexual
relations and only with their wives, the goal being the production of
legitimate offspring and not the pursuit of pleasure. These pronouncements tell
u something about the world in which these three philosophers who made them
lived, and about what men and women in that world were actually doing. Seneca
for example is hardly fulminating about imaginary fices) but they tells us even
more about Cicero, Seneca, and Musoiuns, and their own philosophical
allegiances We have every reason to believe that comments like their rpersented
a minoriy opinion. Indeed, the men AGAINST whom Musonius argues, who believed that
A MASTER has absolute power to do ANYTHING HE WANTS to his slave, is precisel
that man shoes VOICE dominated the public discourse on sexual practice.
Moreover, as Winkler (p. 21) trenchangly observers, Seneca’s condemnation of
such ‘unnatural’ behaviour as growing hothouse flowers or throwing nightime
parties, ‘though articulated as universal, is OBVIOUSLY DIRECTED AT A VERY
SMALL AND WEALTHY ELITE – THOSE WHO CAN AFFORD THE SORT OF LUXURIES Seneca
wants ‘ALL MANKIND’ to do without”, It is telling, too, that Cicero himself
never makes this kind of APPEAL TO NATURA in the SEXUAL INVECTIVE sscattered
throughout the speeches he delivered in the public arenas of the courtroom,
Senate, or popular assembly, and that the argument appears NOWEHERE ELSE IN the
considerable corpus of Seneca’s moral treatises. Likewise, it is worth noting
that Musonius Rufus’s who makes the most extreme case, not only wrote his
treatise in GREEK rather than Latin, as if to underscore its distance from he
everyday beliefs and practices of Romans, but as a philosopher omitted to
stoicis in a way that Cicero and and Seneca are not. As Haexter reminds us,
Cicero proposes manydifferent rhetorical and philosophical positions in his
speeches, letters, and dialogues, and Seneca’s epistles to Lucilius offer a
tentative and experimental mixture of Stoicism and other philosophical schools
(many of his earlier letters end with quotations from Epicurus, for example).
In any case, Boswell, cp. 130 citing ancient sources claiming that the very
founder of stoicism, Zeno, engaged in sexual practices with males (perhaps even
exclusively) tnote that many ancient stoics actually seem to have considered
the question of sexual praticess between males to e ETHICALLY NEUTRAL. Finally,
It is worth noting that both Seneca and Cicero were thought not to have
practiced what they prached. In a discussion of how Seneca’s behaviour often
stood in contracition to his own teachings, the historian DIO CASSIUS observes
that although he married well, Seneca also “takes pleasure in older lads, and
teachers Nero do to the same thing, too”. Dio 61 10 4. Tas te aselgeias has
praton gamon te epiphanestaton egme kai meikarious exorois exaire kai tauto kai
ton Nerona poietin edidaxe. The historian goes on to insutate that Seneca fellated
his partners, speculating on the reason why refused to kiss Nero. One might
imagine, Dio notes, that this was
because he was gisuted by Nero’s penchant for oral sex. But that makes
no sense given Seneca’s own relations with his boyfriends (61 10 5 o gar toi monon an tis hupopteuseien hoti
ouk ethele toiouto stoma philein elegxketai ek ton paidikon autou pseudos on). The younger Pliny (Epist. 7.4) informs us that
Cicero addresses a love poem to his faithful slave and companion Tiro. Of
course neither of these pieces of information tells us anything about Cicero’s
or Seneca’s actual experiences. Cicero’s poem could have been a literary game
and the stories a out Seneca that constituted Dio’s source may well have been
unfounded gossip (For Cicero and Tiro, see McDermott and Richlin. P. 223,
Canatarella p. 103 assumes that they actually ENJOYED A sexual relationship)).
On the other hand, is it not impossible that Cicero actually DID experience
DESIRE for Tiro and that Seneca DID enjoy the company of MATURE MALE SEXUAL
PARTNERS. And abovre all it is important to recognize that later generations of
Romans (the younger Pliny and Dio) were willing to IMAGINE THOSE THINGS
HAPPENING. Dio’s gossipy remarks and Pliny’s comments on Cicero remind us of the cultural context in which a
philosopher’s allusion to NATURA must be placed. Paolo Casini.
Keywords: naturismo, naturalismo, natura, nazione, patto sociale, la legge
naturale, l’uomo, contra natura. “antica sapienza italica” razionalismo, la
metafora della lume, illuminismo, Bruno, il patto sociale -- Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Grice e Casini” – The Swimming-Pool Library.
No comments:
Post a Comment