Grice e Casini: la ragione
conversazionale e l’implicatura conversazionale de naturismo – il concetto di
natura a Roma – scuola di Roma – filosofia romana – filosofia lazia -- filosofia
italiana – Luigi Speranza, pel Gruppo di Gioco di H. P. Grice, The
Swimming-Pool Library (Roma). Filosofo romano. Filosofo lazio. Filosofo
italiano. Roma, Lazio. Grice: “I like Casini – he takes, unlike me,
physics seriously! But then so did Thales, according to Aristotle! – At Clifton
we did a lot of ‘physical’ rather than ‘metaphysical’ education!” – Linceo. Studia a
Roma sotto Nardi, Antoni, e Chabod. Si laurea sotto Spirito (disc. Gregory) con
“L'idea di natura”. I suoi interessi di ricerca in storia della
filosofia si sono successivamente estesi all'intreccio tra filosofia e scienze
sperimentali nel Settecento, soprattutto attorno alla figura di Isaac Newton e
alla diffusione della sintesi newtoniana nella cultura filosofica europea, a
proposito di filosofi come D'Alembert, Buffon, Maupertuis, Clairaut, Eulero,
non senza tener conto dell'opera divulgativa di Voltaire, fino a collocare in
tale contesto Kant. Insegna a Trieste, Bologna, e Roma. Le sue
ricerche riguardano Diderot e la filosofia dell'illuminismo, i nessi tra
rivoluzione scientifica e riflessione filosofica, l'origine e diffusione della
fisica di Newton, le vicende del mito pitagorico tra "prisca
philosophia" e "antica sapienza italica", le dispute sorte
attorno al darwinismo. Altre opere: “Diderot "philosophe",
Laterza); Mecanicismo -- L'universo-macchina: origini della filosofia
newtoniana, Laterza); Rousseau, Laterza); Introduzione all'illuminismo,
Laterza -- razionalismo); Newton e la coscienza europea (Il Mulino); “Progresso
ed utopia” (Laterza); “L'antica sapienza italica. Cronistoria di un mito” (Il
Mulino); “Hypotheses non fingo” (Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura); “Alle
origini del Novecento: "Leonardo", rivista filosofica di Firenze (Il
Mulino); Il concetto di creazione (Il Mulino). La lista di
autorità e l’accenno alla filosofia nazionale preludono al Platone. --Paolo
Casini. Si tratta di un saggio dedicato all'evoluzione del mito
pitagorico nella cultura europea. Senza cadere mai nella rassegna erudita,
l'autore segue passo passo le trasformazioni del mito dalla sua prima
incarnazione nella cultura romana alla riscoperta operata nel Rinascimento,
alle discussioni storico-archeologiche e alle strumentalizzazioni
politiche del Sette-Ottocento. Giuseppe
Bottai o delle ambiguità (Un'erma bifronte - Leader revisionista - Nella babele
corporativa - La guerra di Pisa - «Starci con la mia testa» - Apologia –
Espiazione) - 2. Ugo Spirito: «scienza» e «incoscienza» (Una teoresi
postidealista - Teorico dell'economia corporativa - Il «bolscevico» epurato -
«Mutevolezza e instabilità» - «Scienza», «ricerca», «arte» - Guerra e
Dopoguerra - Alla ricerca del padre) - 3. Camillo Pellizzi: il fascio di Londra
e la sociologia (Genius loci - Tra Roma e Londra - Pax romana in Albione -
«Aristòcrate» - Dottrina del fascismo - Il postfascismo e la «rivouzione
mancata» - Verso la sociologia) - 4. I doni di Soffici («Si parla» - «Scoperte
e massacri» - Sguardi retrospettivi: tragedia e catarsi - Docta ignorantia -
«Commesso viaggiatore dell'assoluto» - Genus irritabile vatum - Un dialogo tra
sordi - Amici e nemici) - 5. Un autoritratto (A metà ventennio – Riflessi - Tra
casa e scuola - Agrari in Toscana - I primi pedagoghi - L'Istituto Massimo sj -
Vinceremo! - Il passaggio del fronte – Dopoguerra - Scuola a Firenze - Al Liceo
Tasso) - 6. Studium Urbis (Gli anni Cinquanta - Nardi e Chabod - Eredità idealistiche
- Ideologie in crisi – Diderot - Roma, gli amici - Savinio, Carocci - La naja –
Intermezzi - Olivetti, Ivrea - La "cultura" della RAI – Let Newton Be
- Anni di prova) - Indice dei nomi Order Zoogonia e
"Trasformismo" nella fisica epicurea Giornale Critico Della Filosofia
Italiana 17 (n/a): 178. 1963. Like Recommend Bookmark L'universo-Macchina
Origini Della Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. 1969. 1 citation
of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 10 Zev Bechler, Newton's Physics and
the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution. Boston Studies in the
Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer
(review) British Journal for the History of Science The
"Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes of ideology Rivista di Filosofia
Political Theory Like Recommend Bookmark Éléments de la philosophie de Newton
(review) British Journal for the History of Science Isaac Newton Like Recommend
Bookmark 10 Rousseau e l'esercizio della sovranità Rivista di Filosofia
Jean-Jacques Rousseau Like Recommend Bookmark 9 Il momento newtoniano in
Italia: un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 2. 2006. Like
Recommend Bookmark 5 Newton in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia Newton 1
citation of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie Arouet de
Voltaire, Éléments de la philosophie de Newton, critical edition by Robert L.
Walters and W. H. Barber. The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15.
Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, Taylor Institution, British Journal for the
History of Science 17th/18th Century French Philosophy Like Recommend Bookmark
Lo spettro del materialismo e la "Sacra famiglia" Rivista di
Filosofia Lumi e utopie in uno studio di Bronislaw Baczko Rivista di Filosofia
The New World and the Intelligent Design Rivista di Filosofia Anti-Darwinist
ApproachesDesign Arguments for Theism Like Recommend Bookmark Scienziati
italiani del Seicento e del Settecento Rivista di Filosofia Kant e la
rivoluzione newtoniana Rivista di Filosofia Kant: Philosophy of Science Like
Recommend Bookmark » Ottica, astronomia, relatività: Boscovich a Roma; «
Rivista di Filosofia Introduzione All'illuminismo da Newton a Rousseau Laterza;
Like Recommend Bookmark Newton e i suoi
biografi Rivista di Filosofia Diderot e Shaftesbury Giornale Critico Della
Filosofia Italiana L'iniziazione Pitagorica Di Vico Rivista di Storia Della
Filosofia; Like Recommend Bookmark Per
Conoscere Rousseau with Jean-Jacques Rousseau Mondadori. 1976. Jean-Jacques
Rousseau Toland e l'attività della materia Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia
British Philosophy, Misc L'eclissi della scienza' Rivista di Filosofia
Rousseau, il popolo sovrano e la Repubblica di Ginevra Studi Filosofici Il mito
pitagorico e la rivoluzione astronomica Rivista di Filosofia Newton, Leibniz e
l'analisi: la vera storia Rivista di Filosofia; Like Recommend Bookmark
13 Francesco Bianchini und die europäische gelehrte Welt um 1700 Early Science
and Medicine History of Science Like Recommend Bookmark L'antica Sapienza
Italica Cronistoria di Un Mito. 1998. Pythagoreans Like Recommend
Bookmark 16 Candide, Theodicy and the «Philosophie de l'Histoire» Rivista
di Filosofia La filosofia a Roma Rivista di Filosofia Vico's initiation into
the study of Pythagoras Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Pythagoreans Topic
Order Teoria e storia delle rivoluzioni scientifiche secondo
Thomas Kuhn Rivista di Filosofia Il
problema D'Alembert Rivista di Filosofia Semantica dell'Illuminismo Rivista di
Filosofia Cheyne e la religione naturale newtoniana Giornale Critico Della
Filosofia Italiana Newton's Physics and
the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution (review) British Journal
for the History of Science Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark 1 Diderot
and the portrait of eclectic philosophy Revue Internationale de Philosophie
Diderot Like Recommend Bookmark 6 "Magis amica veritas": Newton
e Descartes Rivista di Filosofia Isaac Newton Like Recommend Bookmark La Natura
Isedi. 1975. Like Recommend Bookmark Voltaire, la geometria della visione e la
metafisica Rivista di Filosofia Leopardi apprendista: scienza e filosofia
Rivista di Filosofia Studi stranieri sulla filosofia dei Lumi in Italia Rivista
di Filosofia Il metodo di Foucault e le
origini della rivoluzione francese Rivista di Filosofia Rousseau e Diderot
Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Diderot « philosophe » Revue Philosophique de
la France Et de l'Etranger Continental Philosophy 1 citation of this work Like
Recommend Bookmark Newton: gli scolii classici Giornale Critico Della Filosofia
Italiana La ricerca embriologica in Italia da Malpighi a Spallanzani Rivista di
Filosofia L'empirismo e la vera filosofia:
il caso Scinà Rivista di Filosofia 8The Newtonian moment in Italy: A
post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Classical Mechanics Like
Recommend Bookmark 6 James, Freud e il determinismo della psiche Rivista
di Filosofia Freud Grean: Shaftesbury's philosophy of religion and ethics. A
study in enthusiasm (review) Studia Leibnitiana
Herschel, Whewell, Stuart Mill e l'«analogia della natura» Rivista di
Filosofia Newton: the classical scholia History of Science; 1 reference in this
work 15 citations of this work Diderot et le portrait du philosophe éclectique
Revue Internationale de Philosophie Morte e trasfigurazione del testo Rivista
di Filosofia L'universo-Macchina Origini Della Filosofia Newtoniana Laterza. Bechler, Newton's Physics and the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific
Revolution. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 127. Dordrecht: Kluwer
(review) British Journal for the History of Science Éléments de la philosophie
de Newton (review) British Journal for the History of Science 2Isaac Newton
Like Recommend Bookmark 6 The "Enciclopedia italiana". Fringes
of ideology Rivista di Filosofia Political Theory Il momento newtoniano in
Italia: un post-scriptum Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia Rousseau e
l'esercizio della sovranità Rivista di Filosofia Jean-Jacques Rousseau Topic
Order 5 Newton in Prussia Rivista di Filosofia saac Newton 1
citation of this work Like Recommend Bookmark 27 François-Marie Arouet de
Voltaire, Éléments de la philosophie de Newton, critical edition by Robert L.
Walters and W. H. Barber. The Complete Works of Voltaire, 15. Oxford: Voltaire
Foundation, Taylor Institution, (review)
British Journal for the History of Science. 17th/18th Century French
Philosophy. Grice: “An assumption generally shared by those who wrote and read
the tests surveyed in Latin is that male desire can normally and normatively be
directed at either male of female objects. If this configuration is held to be
NORMAL or NORMATIVE, we might expect that it would also be represented as
NAATURAL, and it is thus worthwhile to consider the role played by the
discourse of NATURE in ancient representations of sexual behaviour. This
question is both hughe and complex.Important discussions include Boswell,
1Foucault, 1986, 150-7, 189-227, and Winkler, 20-1 36-7 114 8. but one thing is
clear: the ancient rhetoric of nature, as it relates to sexual practices,
displays significant differenct from more recent discourses. Boswell, for
example, observes that while “what is supposed to have been the major
contribution of Stoicism to Christian sexual morality – the idea that the sole
‘natural’ and hence moral use of sexuality is procreation, is in fact a common
belief of amny philosophies of the day’ at the same time, ‘the term UNNATURAL
was applied eto everything from POSTNATAL CHILD SUPPORT to legal contracts
between friends (Boswell). ‘The objection that homsosexuality is ‘unnatural’
appears, in short, to be neither scientifically nor morally cogent and probably
represents mnothing more than a derogatory epithet of unusual emotiona impact
due to a confluence of historically sanctioned prejudiced and ill-formed ideas
about ‘nature.’”Thus, as Winkler notes, the contrast between nature and
non-nature, when deployed in ancient writings simply ‘does not posess the same
valence that it does today’ Winkler, p. 20 Moreover, nearly all of the texts
that offer opinions on whether specific secual practice is in accordance with
nature are works of philosophy. The guestion does NOT seem to have seriously
engaged the writers of texts that directly spoke to and reflected popular moral
conceptions (e. g. graffiti, comedies, epigram, love poetry, oratory). For this
important distinction between the morallyity espoused by a philosopher and what
we might call popular morality, see the introduction and chapter 1. In short, as Richinlin warns us, the question
I ‘something of a red herring, since the concept of nature takes a larger and
more ominous form in our Christian culture than it did in AAncient Rome,
whetere itw as a matter for philosophers’.Richlin, p. 533. But it may
nonetheless be worthwhile to attempt a preliminary exploration of how the
rhetoric of NATURE was applied by some ROMAN PHILOSOPHERS to sexual practices,
particularly those between males.In other words. I would like to go a step or
two beyond that ‘nature’ is generally used by Roman moralists to justify what
they approve of’ (Edwards 88 n. 87). always bearing in mind, however, that to
the extent that it was mostly taken up by philsoeophers, the question of
‘natural’ sexual practice seems not to have played a significant role in most
public discourse among Romans. Nonphilosophical texts sometimes do deploy the
rhetoric of NATURE in conjunction with sexual practices, at least insofras they
as they offer representations of ANIMAL bheaviour, one possible component in
arguments about what is natural.2-6, and Win3, on Philo’s description of
crocodiles mating. kler, 2See for example Boswell, 137-43, 15 It will come as
no surprise that Roman writers images of animals’ sexual practices are
transparetntly influenced by their own cultural traditions. Thus in no Roman
text do we find an explicit appeal to animal bhehaviour in order to condemn
sexual practices between males as unnatural.Such an argument does occasionally
appear in Greek texts, such as Plato, Laws 836c (martua parag Omenos en ton
therios phusin kai deiknos pros ta toitauta oux aptomenon arena arrenos dia to
me phusei touto einai – and Lucian Amores 36. To Be sure, Musonius Ruffus’s
condemnation of sexual practices between males as para phusin might imply a
reference to animal practices, and it is possible that in some work now lost to
us the Roman Stoic followed in Plato’s footsteps in being explicit on the
point. A Juvenalian satire does make reference to animal behaviour in orer to
condemn cannibalism (claiming that no animas eat member s of their own species
Juv. 15 159-68. And in a passage discussed later in this appendix, Ovid has a
character argue that NO FEMALE ANIMAL experiences SEXUAL DESIRE for other
females. These claims are as unsupportable as the claim that sexual practices
between males do not occur anong nonhuman animals.This is obvious to anyone who
has spent time with dogs. With regard to the academic-study of the question,
the remarks of Wolfe, Evolution and Female Primate Sexual Behaviour, in
Understanding behaviour: what primate studies tell us about human behaviour
Oxford, p.are as illuminating as they are depressing. ‘I have taked with
several (anonymous at their request) primatologists who have told me that they
have observed both male and female homosexual bheaviour during field studies.
They seemed reluctant t publish their data,
however, either because THEY FEARED HOMOPHOBIC REEACTIONS (‘my
ccolleagues might thank that I am gay’) or because they lack a framework for
analysis (‘I don’t know what it means’). On the latter point Wolfe insightfully
comments that the same problem affects our attempts to understand ANY sexual
interactions among primates. ‘Because the alloprimates do not possess language,
it is impossible to inquir into their sexual eroticism. In other words,
homosexual and heterosexual behaviours can be observed, recorded, and analysed,
but we cannot infer either homoeroticism or heteroeroticism from such
behaviours (p. 131). But the fact that we do find animal behaviour cited by
Roman authors to CONDEMN such phenomena as cannibalism and same-sec desire
among females, but not SAME-SEX desire among males, merely proves the point.
These rhetorical strategies reveal more about ROMAN cultural concerns than
about actual animal behaviour. A poem in the Appendix Vergiliana introduces us
to a lover hhappyly separated from his beloved Lydia. In the throes of his
grief he cries out that this miserable fate NEVER BEFALLS ANIMALS: A bull is
never without his cor, nor a he-goat without his mate. In fact, sighs, the
lover: ET MAS QUACUMEQUE EST ILLA SUA FEMINA IUNCAT INTERPELLATOS SUMPAUQM
PLORAVIT AMORES CUR NON ET NOBIS FACILIS NAUTRA FUISTI CUR EGO CRUDELEM PATIOR
TAM SAEPE DOLOREM? (Lydia 35-8). The lover is melodramatically weepy and that
consideration partially accounts of his ridiculous claim that male animals are
never to be seen without their mates. Still, amatory hyperbole aside the verses
nicely illustrate the tendency to shape both natura and animal bheaviour into
whatever form is convenient for the argument at hand. Thus, Ovid,s suggesting
that the best way to appease one’s angry mistress is in bed, portrays sexual
behaviour among early human beings and animals s as the primary force that
effects RECONCILIATION (Ars 2 461-92. The poet offers a lovely panorama in
which animal behaviour is invoked as a POSTIIVE paradigm for specific human
practices: unting otherwise scattered groups (2. 473-80) and mollifying an
angry lover (2. 481-90). Less than two hundred lines later, the same poet
invokes animalas as A NEGATIVE PARADIGM, again in support of a
characteristically human concern: discretion in sexual matters. IN MEDIO
PASSIMQUE COIT PECUS HOC QUOQUE VISO AVETIT VULTUS NEMPE PUELLA SUOUS
CONVENIUNS THALAMI FURTIS ET IANUA NOSTRIS PARSQUE SUB INJIECAT VESTE PUDDAN
LATET ET SI NON TENEBRAS AT QUIDDAM NUBIS OPACAE QUAERIMUS ATQUE ALIQUID LUCE
PATENTE MINUS (Ovid, Ars, 2 615-20). Drawing his objets lesson to a close, Ovid
holds up his own behaviour as a pattern to follow. NOS ETIAM VEROS PARCE
PROFITEMUR AMORES TECTAQUE SUNT SOLIDA MYSTIFCA FURTA FIDE 639-40. And we are
reminded of the strategies of this pasage’s broader context. If you want to
keep your girlfriend happy, do not kiss and tell: that is the argument in
service of which animal behaviour is invoked as NEGATIVE paradigm. These to
Ovidian passages illustrate the utilyt of arguments from the animal world. Just
look ant the animals and see how much we resemble them; just look at the51-5. animals and see how far we have come.An
epigram by theGreek poet Strato gives the later poin an dineresting twist. We
huam beings, he writes, are SUPERIOR to animals in that, in addition to vaginal
intercourse, we have discovered ANAL INTERCOURSE, thus men who are dominated by
women are really no better than mere animals (A P 12 245 PAN ALOGON soon bivei
monon oi ligkoi de ton allon zoon tout exkomen to pleon pugizein eurotntes
hosoi de guanxi kratountai ton alogon zoon ouden exousi kleon. It all depends
on the eye – and rhetorical needs – of the beholder. OS it is that Roman
writers show how Roman they are through the picture they paint of sexual
practices among animals of the same sex. Ovid himself, in his Metamorphoses,
imagines the plight of young girl named Iphis who has fallen in love with
another girl. In a torrent of self-pity and self-abuse, she expostulates on her
passion, making a simultaneous appeal to NATURA and to the animals that is
reminiscent of Ovid’s sweeping review of animal bheaviour in the Ars amatorial
just cited. But this time the paradigm is an emphatically negative one. SI DI
MIHI PARCERE VELLENT PARCERE DEBUERANT SI NON ET PERDERE VELLENT NAUTRALE MALUM
SALTEM ET DE MORE DEDISSENT NEC CACCAM VACCA NEC EQUAS AMOR URIT EQUARUM: URIT
OVES ARIES SEQUITUR SUA FEMINA CERVUM SIC ET AVES COEUNT INTERQUE ANIMALIA
UNCTA FEMINA FEMINEO ONREPTA CUPIDINE NULLA EST (Ov. Met. 9. 728-34) As with
Lydia’s lover, so here we have the melodramatic expostulations of an unah[py
lover, and similarly her view of animal behaviour does not correspond to the
realities of that behaviour. Still, these arguments are pitched in such a way
as to invite a Roman reader’s agreement, and the sexual practices invoked as
natural and occurring among the animals demonstrate a SUSPICIOUS SIMILARTY to
the sexual practices and desired SEMMED ACCEPTABLE BY ROMAN CULTURE (the female
never leaves the male, heterosexual intercourse is a convenient and pleasurable
way of unting different social groups, and females never lust after females),
or to specifically HUMAN EROTIC STRATEGIES: we do not copulate in public, and
we should not kiss and tell if we want our to keep our partners happy. It
cannot be coincidental that, whereas Ovid invokes animal behaviour in the
context of a girl’s tortured rejection of her own passionalte yearnings for
another girl, the mythic compendium in which this natrratie is found is
peppered with stories involves passion and sexual relations between males. Both
Orfeo (after losing his wife Euridice) and the gods themselves (whether married
or not) are represented as ‘giving over their love to TENDER MALES, harvesting
the BRIEF springtime and its first flowers before maturaity sets in” Ov. Met.
10. 83-5 ORPHEUS ETIAM THRACUM POPULIS FUIT AUCTOR AMORET IN TENEROS TRANSFERRE
MARES CITRAQUE IUVENTAM AETATIS BREVE VER ET PRIMOS CARPERE FLORES. The stories
that Orfeo proceeds ts to relate include those of the young CYPARISSUS once
loved by Apollo Met 10.106-42 and the tales of Zeus and Ganumede, Apollo and
Hyacinth (Met 10 155-219 Consider also the beautiful sixteen yer old Indian boy
Athis and his Assyrian lover Lycabas (Met. 5 47-72. A passage which echoes of
Virgil’s lines on NISUS AND EURIALO discussed in chapter 2. And the remark that
the stunning but haughty young Narcissus, also in his sixteenth year, had many
admireers of both sexses (Met. None of Ovid’s characters arever questions the
NATURAL status of that kind of erotic experience or invokes the animals in
order to reject it. Aulus Gellius preserves for us some anecdotes that further
demonstrate the manner in which animal bheaviour could be made to conform to
human paradigms. Writing of (IMPLICITLY MALE) dolfns who fell in love with
beautiful boys (one oft them even died of a broek heart after losing his
beloved) Gellius exclaims that they were acing “in amazing human ways” 606C-D
and Plin N H 8 25-8 for this and other tales of male dolphins falling in love
with human boys. Gell 6 8 3 NEQUE HI AMAVERUNT QUOD SUNT IPSI GENUS SED PUEROS
FORMA LIBERALI IN NAVICULIS FORE AUT IN VADIS LITORUM CONSPECTOS MIRIS ET
HUMANIS MODIS ARSERUNS. Cf. Athen 13 Once again, the comment tells us more
about ‘human ways’ than about dolphins. The elder Plini, who alo relates this
story regarding the dolphin, introduces his encyclopeic discussion of elephants
by observing that they are nonly the largest land animals but the ones closest
to human beings in their intelligence and sense of morality. In particular,
they take pleasure in love and pride (AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS), and by way
of illustration of the ‘power of love’ (AMORIS VIS) among elephants he cites two
examples: ONE MALE FELL IN LOVE WITH A FEMALE FLOWER_SELLER, another with a
young Syractusan man named MENANDER who was in Ptolemy’s army. Likehise he
tells of a MALE GOOSE who fell in love with a beautiful young Greek MAN, and of
another who loved a female musician whose beauty as such that she alstro
attracted the attention of a ram. -4. NEC QUIA DESIT ILLIS AMORIS VIS, NAMQUE
TRADITUR UNUS AMASSE QUANDAM IN AEGYPTO COROLLAS VENDENTEM ALLUS MENANDRUM
SYRACUSANUM INCIPIENTIS IUVENTAE IN EERCITU PTOLEMACI DESIDERIUM EIUS QUOTIENS
NON VIDERET INEDIA TESTATUS 10.51 QUIN EST FAMA AMORS AEGII DILECTA FORMA PUERI
NOMINE OLENII AMPHILOCHI, ET GLAUCES PTOLOMAEO REGI CITHARA CANENTIS QUAM EODEM
TEMPORE ET ARIES AMASSE PRODITUR. Plin N H 8 1. MAXIMUM EST EPLEPHANS PROXIMUMQUE
HUMANIS SENSIBUS QUIPPE INTELLECTUS ILLIS SERMONIS PATRII ET IMPERIORUM
OBEDIENTIA, OFFICIOURM QUAE DIDICERE MEMORIA, AMORIS ET GLORIAE VOLUPTAS 8 13Turing
to the concept of NATURA as it applied to sexual pracyices by ancient writers,
we being with basica basic problem. The very term NATURA has various referents
in those texts. Sometimes NATURA seems simply to refer to the way things are or
to the INHERENT nature OF something, sometimes to the way things SHOULD be
according to the intention ordictates of some transcendent imperative. Thus
Foucault speaks of ‘the ‘three axes of nature’ in philosophical discourse. The
general order of the world, the orgginal state of mankind, and a behaviour that
is reasonably adapted to natural ends.Fouctault, p. 215-6. See also the
discussions in Boswell, p. 11-5, where he distinguishes between ‘realistic’ and
‘ideal’ notions of nature, Beagon, and Levy, “Le concept de nature a Rome: la
physique, Paris). The first two of these axes are evident in a wife-variety of
Roman texts. Departures from what is observably the usual PHYSICAL constitution
of various thbeings could be called NONNATURAL or UNNATURAL even by
nonphilosophical authors. The Minotuar, centaurs, a snake with feet, a bird
with four wings, and a sexual union between a woman (the muthis Pasiphae) and a
bull.snAnon De Differentiis 520 23 MONSTRUM EST CONTRA NATURAM UT EST
MINOTAURUS. Serv. Aen 6. 286 (centaurs) Suet Prata fr. 176.113-5 snakes with feet, birds with four wings.
Serv. Aen. 1. 235.11. Pasiphae and the bull. Te elder Plinty claims that breech
births are ‘against nature’ since it is ‘nature’s way’ that we should be born
head first.n N H 7 45 -6. IN PEDES PROCIDERE NASCENTEM CONTRA NATURAM EST RITUS
NATURAE CAPITE HOMINEM GIGNI MOST EST PEDIBUS EFFERRI. PLiQuintilian argues
that to push one’s hair back from the forehead in order to achieve some
dramatic effect is to act ‘against nature’.Quint I O 11 3 160 CAPILLOS A FRONTE
CONTRA NATURAM RETRO AGERE. and Seneca himself opines that being carried about
in a litter is ‘contra natural’a, since nature has gives us feet and we should
use them.Sen. Epist 55 ` LABOR EST ENIM ET DIU FERI AC NESCIO AN EO MAIOR QUIA
CONTRA NATURAM EST QUAE PEDES DEDIT UT PER NOS AMBULAREMUS. Finally, the belief
that physical disabilities and disease are UNNAUTARAL, and thus, implicitly,
that a healthy body displaying no marked derivations from the form illustrates
what nature designed or intended, surfaces in a number of texts, arnign from
Celusus’ mdical treatise to Ciceroo’s philosophical works to declamations
attributed to Quintilian, to a moral epistle fo Seneca to the, to the Digest.2
1. 60 pr. MOTUS CORPORIS CONTRA NATURAM QUAM FEBREM
APPELLANT. Quint. Decld. Min. 298.12 WEAK AND MALFORMED BODIES ARE IMPLICITLY
CCONTRA NATURAM. Celsus Medic 3 21 15. On fluids that are retained in the body
contra naturam. Cic Off 3 30 MORBUS EST CONTRA NATURAM. Gell. 4 2 3 Labeo
defines morbus asHABITUS CUIUSQUE CORPORIS CONTRA NATURAM QUI USUUM ETIUS FACIT
DETERIOREM. Cf. D. 21 1 1 7. D. 4Along the same lines, some ancient writers
also suggest that to harm a healthy body with poisons and the like is unnatural.Quint
Decl. Min. 246.3 the plaintiff refers to a substance as a venenum QUONIAM
MEDICAMENTUM SIT ET EFFICIAT ALIQUID CONTRA NATURAM. Sen Epist 5. 4. To torment
one’s body and to eat unhealthy food is CONTRA NATURAM. As for the third of the
axes described by Foucault, anthropologists and others have long observed that
proclamations concerning practices that are in acoordance with nature often
turn out to reflect specific cultural traditions. As Winkler puts it, for nature
we may often read culture.Winkler p. 17. In the same way Edwards p. 87-8
discusses a passage from Seneca (Epist 95.20=1) discussed in chapter 5, having
to do with women who violate their ‘nature.’ She concludes that ‘Seneca was not
reacting to naturally anomalous bheaviour. He was taking part in the
reproduction of a a cultural system.’ So too Veyne , p. 26. ‘When an ancient
says that something is unnatural, he does not mean that it is disgraceful
(monstrueuse) that that it does not conform with the rules of society, or that
it is perverted OR ARTIFICIAL”. Roman sources of various types certainly
support that contention. Thus, for example, violations of traditional
PRINCIPLELS OF LANGUAGE AND RHETORIC which are surely among the most intensely
cutlrual of human phenomeno are SOMETIMES SAID TO BE UNNATURAL.Serv. Comm. Art
Don. 4 4 4 PLINIUS AUTEM DICIT BARBARISMUM ESSE SERMOVEM UNUM IN QUO VIS SUA
EST CONTRA NATURAM – Serv Aen. 4. 427. REVELLI NON REVULSI. NAM VELLI ET REVELLI DICIMUS. VULSUS VERO ET REVULSUS USURPATUM EST TANTUM
IN PARTICIPIIS CONTRA NATURAM cf. Sen. Contr. 10, pr. 9 –
tof the rhetorician Musa. OMNIA USQUE AD ULTIMUM TUMOREM PERDUCTA UT NON EXTRA
SANITATEM SED EXTRA NATURAM ESSENT. One legal writer invokes the rhetoric of
NATURA to justify the principle of individual ownership (joint possession of a
single object is said to be CONTRA NATURAL.D. 41 2 3 5 CONTRA NATURAM QUIPPE
EST UT CUM EGO ALIQUID TENEAM TU QUOTE ID TENERE VIDEARIS. Interestingly,
another jurist argues that the principle underlying the institution of slavery
– that one person can be owned by another – is actually ‘unnatural’ (D. 1. 5.
4. 1. SERVITUS EST CONSTITUTIO IURIS GENTIUM QUA QUIS DOMINIO ALIENO CONTRA
NATURAM SUBICITUR. In a Horatioan satire we read that NATURA sees it that no
one is every truly the ‘master’ of the land that he legally owns, and Natura
puts a limit on how much one can inherit (Hor. Sat. 2. 2. 129-30, 2.3.178). Sallust
describes the violation of the cultural and more specifically philosophical
tradition priviliengy the SOUL over the BODY as UNNATRUAL.Sall. Cat. 2. 8.
QUIVUS PROFECT CONTRA NATURAM CORPUS VOLUPTATI, ANIMA OVERI FUIT. SALLUST.
Likewise, practices violating Roan ideologies of MASCULINITY are represented as
INFRACTIONS NOT of cultural tranditions s but of the natural order. Cicero’s
philosophical tratise DE FINIBUS includes a discussion of the parts and with
some clarity functions of the BODY that illustrates the relation between NATURE
and MSASCULINITY with some clarity Our bodily parts, Cicero argues, are
PERFECTLY DESIGNED to fulfil their functions, and in doing so they are in
conformance with nature. But there are certain bodily movesmesns NOT in accord
with nature (NATURAE CONGRUENTES> If a man were to walk on his hand or to
walk backwyasds, he would manifestbly be rejecgting his identity as a human and
thuswould thus be displayeing a ‘hattred of nature’ (NAUTRAM ODISSE). Cic Fin 5
35. CORPORIS IGITUR NOSTRI PARTES TOTAQUE FIGURA ET FORMA ET STATURA QUAM APTA
AD NATURAM SIT APPARET. The claim that walking on one’s hand is unnatural
nicely illustrates the gap between ancient and more recent uses of the rhetoric
of nature – cfr. Dodgson). The next illustration Cicer o offers of bodily
moveents not in accord with natura concerns correctly masculine ways of
deporing oneself. QUAMOBREM ETIAM SESSIONES QUAEDAM ET FLEXI FRACTIQUE MOTUS,
QQUALES PROTERVORUM HOMINUM AUT MOLLIUM ESSE SOLENT, CONTRA NATURAM SUNT, UT
ETIAMSI ANIMI VITIO ID EVENIANT TAMEN IN CORPOMUTRAR MUTARI HOMINIS NATURA
VIDEATUR ITAQUE A CONTRARIO MODERATI AEQUABILESQUE HABITUS AFFECTIONS USUSQUE
CORPORIS APTI ESSE AD NAUTRAM VIDENTUR (Cic. Fin 5. 35-6. Deemed ‘agaist
natture’ are certain ways of carrying oneself that are ‘wanton’ and ‘soft,’
movements lthat, like walking on one’s hand or stepping backwards, clasi the
with thvident purporse of the body’s various parts. Implicitly then, nature
wills men’s bodies to move and to function in certain ways. Men who violate
these principles of masculine comportment are acting BOTH EFFEMINATELY (as we
saw in chapter 4, militia is a standard metaphor for effeminacy) AND
UNNATURALLLY. Cultural traditions regarding masculinity – here, appropriate
bodily gestures – are identified with the natural order.Similar conddemnations
of inappropriate bodily comportment, marked as EFFEMINATE, abound: walking
daintily, scratching the hair delicately wih onefinger, and so on (see chapter
4 in general and see Gleason for a general discussion of physiognomy and
masculinity in antiquity. How, then is the rheotirc of nature applied to
same-sex practices? One scholar has recently suggested that the elder Pliny
describes men’s desires to be anally penetrated as occurring ‘by crime against
nature’ Taylor, p. 325. But that is probably a misinterpretation of Pliny’s
language. IN HOMINUM GENERE MARIBUS DEVERTICULA VENERIS EXCOGIGATA OMNIA,
SCLERE (or CCCELERE naturae FEMINIS VERO AOBRTUS Plin N H 10 172. The phrase
DEVERTICULA VENERIS which one might translate (by-ways of sex’ or ‘sexual
deviations’ is vague. There is no reason to think that it refers to
specifically, let alone exclusively, to the practice of being anally
penetrated. Moreover, the phrase SCELERA NATURA or SCELERE NATURAE, rather than
‘crime against nature,’ is most obviously transated as ‘crime OF NATURE,’ that
is, a crime perpetrated BY NATURE.This is indeed the way Plinio uses the phrase
elsewhere, noting that we ought to call earthquakes ‘moracles of the eart
rather than crimes of nature’ (NH 2 206 – UT TERRAE MIRACULA POTIUS DICAMU QUAM
SCLEREA NATURAE. See Beagon, p. 29. In other words (pace Taylor and Rackham
Loeb Classical Library translation, I take the genitive NATURAE to be
subjective rather than objective. I have not found any parallels for such an
objective use of a genitive noun dependent upon scelus. In any case, Pliny is
not implying that all sexual desires or practices between males are unnatural:
in this same treatise, significantly called the HISTORIA NAUTRALIS or Natural
Investigations’ he reports the story of a male elephant who fell passionately
in love with a young man from Syractuse as an illustration of the obviously
natural power of love of love (amoris vis) among elephants; likewise, he
reports the story of a gosse who loved a beautiful young man.Plin N H 8 13-4,
10.51More explicitly referring to those men who take pleasure in being
penetrated, the speaker in Juvenal’s second satire riducules menwho have
wilfully abandoned their claim on masculine status by weaking makeup,
participating in women’s religious festivals, and even taking husbands, and
notes with gratitude, that nature does not allow them gto give birth.Juv. 2 139
40. SED MELIUS QUOD NIL ANIMIS IN CORPORI IURIS NATURA INDULGET STERILES
MORTUNTUR. For Further discussion see Appendix 2. The orator Labienus decries
wealthy men who castrate their male prostitutes (EXOLETI, see chapter 2) in
order to render them more suitable for playing the receptice role in
intercourse. These men use their rinces in UNNATURAL WAYS (contra natural), and
the natural standard they they violate is apparently the principle that mature
males both should make use of the PENISES and should be IMPENETRABLE.Sen Contr.
10. 4 17. PRINCIPES VIRI CONTRA NATURAM DIVITIAS SUAS EXERCENT CASTRATORUM
GREGES HABENT EXOLETOS SUOS AD LONGIOREM PATIENTIALM IMPUDICITIAE IDONEI SINT
AMPUTANT. Firmicus Maternus refers to men’s desires to be penetrated as CONTRA
NATURAL (5. 2. 11), and Caelius Aurelianus’s medical wirtings also reveal the
assumption that men’s ‘natural’ sexual function is TO PENETRATE and not to be
penetrated. NATURALIA VENERIS OFFICIA. Cael. Aurel. Morb. Chron. 4 In short,
nature’s ditactes conveniently accorded with cultural traditions, such as those
discouraging men from seeking to be penetrated, or those deterring them from
engaging in sexual relations with other men’s wives: in a poem that urges on
its male readers the principle that NATURA places a limit of their desires,
Horace remocommends, as implicitly being in line with the requirement of
nature, that men avoid potentially dangerous affaris with married women and
stick to their own slaves, bh male and female.Hor. Sat.. NONNE CUPIDINIBUS
STATUAT NATURA MODUM QUEM … Se chapter 1 for further discussion of this poem. Cf. Sat. 1.
4. 113-4: NE SEQUERER MOECHAS CONCESSA CUM VENERE UTI POSEEM. In one of his Episles Seneca provides a lengthy and revealing discussion
of ‘unnatural’ behavours that include a reference to sexual practices among
males. He beings, however, by despairing of ‘those who have perverted the roles
of daytime and nightime, not opening their eyes, weighed down by the preceding
day’s hangover, until night begins its approach. Sen Epist 122 2 SUNT QUI
OFFICIA LUCIS NOTISQUE PERVERTERINT NEC ANTE DIDUCANT OCULOS HESTERNA GRAVES
CRAPULA QUAM ADPETERE NOX COEPIT. These people are objectionably not simply
because of their overindulgence in goof and drink but because they do not
respect the proper function of night and day.Comparing them to the Antipodes,
mythincal beings who live n the opposite side of the globe, he asks. Do you
think these people know HOW to live when they don’t even know WHEN to live?
122.3 HOS TU EXISTIMAS SCIRE QUEMADMODUM VIVENDUM SIT QUI NESCIUNT QUANDO?and
this pervesion of night and say, is, in the end, ‘unnatural’. INTERROGAS
QUOMODO HAEC ANIMAO PRAVITAS FIAT AVERSANDI DIEM ET TOTAM VITAM IN NOCTEM
TRANSFERENDI? OMNIA VITA CONTRA NAUTRAM PUGNANT, OMNIA DEBITUM ORDINEM DESERUNT
(Sen Epist.). He then proceeds to tick off a serioes of bheaviour
that are similarly CONTRA NATURAM. First, people who drink on an empty stomach
‘live contrary to nature’ Sen. 122 6 NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA NATURAM VIVERE
QUI IEIUNI BIBUNT QUI VINUM RECIPIUNT INANIBUS VENIS ET AD CIBUM EBRII
TRANSEUNT. Young men nowadsays, Seneca continues, go to the baths before a meal
and work up a sewat by drinking heavily; according to them, only hopelessly
philistine hicks (patres familiae rustici … et verae volupatigs ignari) save their
drinking for after the meal.Sen Epist 122 6. ATQUI FREQUENS HOC ADULESCENTIUM
VITIUM EST QUI VIRES EXCOLUNT UT IN IPSO PAENE BALINEI LIMINE INTER NUDOS
BIBANT IMMO POTENT ET SUDOREM QUEM MOVERUNT POTIONIBUS CREBRIS AC FERVENTIBUS
SUBINDE DESTRINGAT POST PRANDIUM AUT CENAM BIBERE VULGARE ETS HOC PATRIS
FAMILIAE RUSTICI FACIUT ET VERA VOLUPTATIS IGNARI. The latter comment, with its
contrast between URBAN AND RUSTIC life, austerity and luxyry , is a valuable
reminder of us. The standard violated by those who drank betweofre eating was
what we would call a cultural norm. But for Seneca they were violating the
dicates of NATURE, abandoning the proper order (debitum ordinem) of things.
This important point bust be borne in mind as we turn to the next practices
that come under Seneca’s fire: NON VIDENTUR TIBI CONTRA NATURAM VIVERE QUI
OMMUTANT CUM FEMINIS VESTEM? NON VIVUNT CONTRA NAUTRA QUI SPECTANT UT
PUERITIA SPENDEAT TEMPORE ALIENO? QUID FIERI CRUDELIS VEL VISERIOUS POTEST?
NUMQUAM VIR ERIT, UT DIU VIRUM PATI POSSIT? ET CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE SEXUS
ERIPUISSE DEBUERANT NON NE AETAS QUIDEM ERIPIET (Sen. Epist 122. 7). The concept of the proper order is very much in evidence here, and
here again the order shows unmistakable signs of cultural influence. Just as
those who turn night into day or drink wine before they eat a meal are engaging
in unnatural activities, so men who wear women’s clothes live contrary to
nature – yet what could be more cultural than the designation of certain kinds
of clothing as appropriate only for men and others as appropriate only for
women? Moving on to his next point, Senceca continues to focus on extermal
appearance. Men who attempt to give the appearance of the boyhood that is in
fact no longer theirs also ‘live contrary to nature’. Again the order of things
has been disrputed. Boys should be boys, men should be men. But these particular
men want to LOOK like boys in order to find older male sexual partners to
penetrate them. Such is the thenor of Seneca’s decorous but blunt phrase, ‘so
that he may submit to a man for a long time’ (ut diu virum pati possit’). If we
filter out Seneca’s moralizing overlay, this detail gives us a fascinating
fglimpse oat Roman realities. These MEN scorned by Seneca acted upon the
awareness that MEN would be more likely to find them desirable if their bodies
seemed like those of BOYS (not men): young, smooth, irless. Moreover, the very
fact that these men made the effort suggests that th actual age of the
beautiful ‘boys’ we always hear of may not have mattered to their loveers so
much as their youthful APPEARANCE.Cf. Boswell, p. 29, 81. All of this is very
much a matter of CONVENTION, of CULtURAL traditions concerning the ‘proper
order’ of things, but Seneca insistently pays homage to NATURA.Cf. Winkler, p.
21. “Contrary to nature means to Senea not ‘outside the order of the kosmos’
but ‘unwilling to conform to the simplicity of the unadorned life’ and, in the case
of sex, ‘going AWOL rom one’s assigned place in the social hierarchy’”. The
importance of this order is especially clear in the climactic illustrations of
those who live ‘contrary to nature’. These are people who wish to see see roses
in winter and employ artificial means to grow lilies in the cold season; who
grow orchards at the tops of towers and trees under the roofs of their homes
(this latter proving Seneca to a veritable outburst ofm moral indignation).,
and those who construct their bathhouses over the waters of the sea Sen. Epist
122 21 NON VIVUNT CONTRA NATURAM QUI FUNDAMENTA THERMARUM IN MARI IACIUNT ET
DELICATE NATARE IPSI SIBI NON VIDENTUR NISI CALENTIA STAGNA FLUCT AC TEMPESTATE
FERIANTUR. Finally Seneca returns to the
example of unnatural practices that sparked the whole discussion: those who
pervert the function of night and day aengage in the ultimate form of unnatural
behaviour (Sen Epist 122 9 CUM INSTITUERUNT OMNIA CONTRA NATURAE CONSUETUDINEM
VELLE NOVISSIME IN TOTUM AB ILLA DESCISCUNT LUCET SOMNI TEMPUS EST QUIES EST
NUNC EXERCEAMUR NUNC GESTEMUR NUNC PRANDEAMUS. That the practice ofs of growing
trees indoors, of building bathhouses over the sea, and of sleeping by day and
partying by night should be considered unnatural makes some sense in relation
to notions of the ‘proper order’ of things. Plants should e outdoors, buldings
should be on dray land, and people should sleep at night. But that thes
practices should be cited as the most egregious examples of unnatural bheaviour
– they constitute the climax of Seneca’s argument – demontrastes just how wide
the gap is between ancient moralists and their modern counterparts on the
question of what is natural. With regard to mature men who seek to be
penetrated by men, the third of Seneca’s examples of unnatural behaviour,
Seneca makes in passing a surprising remark. CUM ILLUM CONTUMELIAE SEXUS ERIPUISSE DEBUERAT NON NE AETAS QUIDEM ERIPIET?
122.7. The clear implication is that a nature man
certainly ought to be safe from ‘indignity’ (here a moralizing euphemism for
penetration), but ultimately the very fact that he is MALE, REGARDLESS OF HIS
AGE, ought to protect him. With with one pointed sentence, then, Seneca is
suggesting that MALENESS IN ITSELF IS IDEALLY INCOMPATIBLE WITH BEING
PENETRATED, and since sexual acts were almost without exception conceptualized
as REQUIRING penetration, this amounts to positing the exclusion of sexual practices
BETWEEN MALES from the ‘proper order’. This is a fairly radical suggestion FOR
A ROAM MAN TO MAKE, and Seneca was no doubt aware of that fact. He slips the
comment quietly into his discussion, makes the point rather subtly (it makight
ake a second reading even to REALISE IT IS THERE), and then instantly moves on
to other, less controversial arguments. FOR as opposed to Seneca’s suggestion
that EVERY MALE, even a boy, should somehow be ‘rescued’ from ‘indignity,’ the
usual Roman system of protocols governing men’s sexual behaviour required the
understanding that A BOY is different from A MAN precisely because they COULD
BE penetrated without necessarily forfeiting EVERY CLAIM to masculine or male
status (see especially chapter 5 on this last point). But Seneca, waxing Stoic,
here voices a dissenting opinion, as does the first century A. D. Stoic
philosopher MUSONIUS RUFUS, in one of twhose treatises we find the remark that
sexual practices BETWEEN MALES are ‘against nature’ (‘para-physical’) Muson,
Ruf. 86. 10 Lutz para phusin. The remark needs to be be put in the context of
Musonius’s philosophy of nature. According to Musonious, every createure has its own TELOS beyond the goal
of simply being aalive En a horse would not b e fully living up to its telos if
all it did was to eat, drink, and copulate (106.25-7 Lutz)., while the TELOS or
goal of a human being is to live the life or arete or VIRTUS. Thus, “each one’s
nature (phusis) leads him to his particular virtuous quality (arete), so that
it is is a reasonable conclusion that a human being is living in accordance
WITH nature NOT when he lives in pleasure, but rather when he lives in virtue” 108.1-3
Lutz). Elsewhere he opines that human nature (phusis – anthropine phusis,
natura humana, Hume, Human Nature) is not aimed at pleasure (hedone, 106.21.3
Lutz). Consequently, luxury (truphe) is to be avoided in EVERY way, as being
the cause of INJUSTICE (126.30-1 Lutz). By implication, then, eating, drinking,
and aopulating are not in themselves evil, but they can easily become sgns of a
life of luxury, and if those activities aconstitute the goals of our existence,
we are FAILING TO FULFIL OUR POTENTIAL AS A HUMAN BEING, namely, the practice
of virtue, or reason, and consequently, not living IN ACCORDANCE WITH NATURE,
but against her (paa phusin). Thus, as part of a regime of SELF-CONTROL
(MALENESS OR MASCULINITY AS SELF-CONTROL, not addictive behaviour or weakness
of the will) Musonius argues that a man should engage in a sexual practice only
within the context of marriage for the purpose of begetting children. Any other
sexual relation, even within marriage should be avoided. T”Those who do not
live licentiously, or who are not evil, must think that only those sexual
practices are justified which are consummated within marriage and for the
creation of children, since these pratcttices are licit (NOMIMA). But such
people must think that those sexual practices which hunt for mere pleasure are
unjust and illicit, even if they take place within marriage. Of Other forms of
intercourse, those committed in moikheia (I e. a sexual relation with a
freeborn woman under another man;s control) are the most illicit. No more
moderate than this is the INTERCOURSE OF MALES WITH MALES, since it is a DARING
ACT CONTRARY TO NATURE. As for those forms of intercourse with with females
apart from moikheia which are not licit (kaTa nomon) all of these are too
shameful, because done on account of a lack of self-control. If one utside to behave temperately (TEMPERANTIA,
CONTINENTIA) one would not dare to have relations with a courtesan, nor with a
free woman outside of marriage, nor, by Zeus, with one’s own slave woman
(Musonius Rufus, 86.4-14 Lutz). As I argued in chapter 1, Musonius’s final
remark reveals the extent to which the sexual morality that he is preaching is
at odds with mainstream Roman traditions. Nor is his suggestion that men should
keep their hans off prostitutes and their own slaves the only surprising
statement to be found in the treatises attributed to Musonius. He elsewhere
aargues against the obviously widespread practices of giving up for adoption or
even exposing unwanted children (96-97 Lutz), of EATING MEANT (here he
explicitly contrasts himself with the many hoi polloi who live to eat rather
than the other way around (118-18-20 Lutz) or SHAVING THE BEARD (128.4-6 Lutz),
of using wet nurses (42.5-9 Lutz), and most appositely, of allowing husbands
sexual freedoms not granted to wives (96-8 Lutz). Thus his condemnation of
sexual practices between MALES is issued in the context of a condemnation of
ALL SEXUAL PRATICES other than those between husband and wife aimed at
procreation (strictly speaking, vaginal intercourse when the wife is ovulating)
and also in the context of a a suspicion of all luxury oand of pleasures beyond
those relating to the bare necessities of life. Thus he condemns sexual
relations between males as contrary to nature (the implication being that the
two sexes ARE DESIGNED TO UNITE WICH EACH OTHER IN THE CONTEXT OF MARRIAGE),
while sexual relations between malesand female outside of marriage are
criticized as ‘illicit (para-noma) and as signs of lack of self-control. Here
Musonius is obviously manipulating the ancient contrast between law or
convention (nomos) and nature (phusis) and interprestingly procreative
relations within marriage are ultimately given his seal of approval not because
they are more ‘natural’ than tother sexual practices, but because they are
‘licit’ or ‘conventional’ (nomima), just as adulterious relations are most
‘illicit’ of unconventional (paranomotatai). In other words, Musonius invokes
the rhetoric of nature only by way of secondary support.. A male-male relation
is no more ‘moderate’ than a adulterious relationa dn anyway, he adds, they are
‘unnatural’. But a relation between a man and another man’s wife, while
implicitly ‘natural’,is in the end more ‘illicit’ than a male-male relation.
Even for the Stoic Musonious, NATURA may NOT be the ultimate arbiter.
Interestingly, when he describes sexual practices between males as being
against nature, Musonius does not appeal to animal bheaviour as does Plato in
his Laws (836c). Indeed, such an argument sould have ill-suited Musonius’s
argument elsewhere that humans are different from other animals and should not
takem them as a MODEL FOR BHEAVIOUR. Thus he argues that wise men ill not
attack in return if attacked – such revenge is the province of MERE ANIMALS –
78.26-7 Lutz) – and that, while among animals an act of copulation suffices to
procude offspring, human beings should aim for the lifelong union that is
marriage (88.16-17 Lutz). Finally, there is an important distinction to observe
between Musonius’s remark concerning sexual practices between males and later
Christian fulminations against ‘the unnatural vice’ which came to be a code
term for ‘sodomy’. On the one hand, Musonius did not go so far as to condemn
such relations as THE unnatural vice. Indeed, if we think about the
implications of his words, relations between MALES do not even constitute the
ULTIAMTE sexual crime. He declare that ADULTEROUS relations are ‘the most
illicit of all’ (paranomotatai) and thus clearly more ‘illicit’ than relations
between males which are howevery ‘equally immoderate’. Furthermore Musonius’s
approach to the problem of sexual behaviour differs from later Christian
moralists in a fundamental respect. As Foucault puts it, according to Musonius,
‘to withdraw pleasure from this form (sc. Of marriage, to detach pleasure from
the conjugal relation in order to propoeseother ends for it, is in fact to debase
the ESSENTIAL composition of the human being. The defilement is not in the
sexual act itself, but in the ‘debauchery’ that would dissociate it from
marriage, where it has its natural form and its rational purpose” Foucault p.
170. Cicero ro in a passage from one of this major philosophical works, the
Tusculan disputations, approaches the ascetic stance advocated by Seneca and
Musonius Rufus, although he nowhere makes an explicit commitment to the extreme
suggested by Seneca and preached by Musonius. Speaking in the Tusculan
Disputations of the detrimental effects of erotic passion, Cicero observes that
the works of Greek poets are filled with images of love. Focusing on those who
describe LOVE FOR BOYS (he mentions Alcaeus, Anacreon, and Ibycus), Cicero
notes thain an aside that ‘NATURE HAS GRANTED A GREATER PERMISSIVENESS (maiorem
liicnetial)” to men’s affairs with women. Cic. Tusc. 4. 71. ATQUE UT MULIEBRIS
AMORES OMITTAM QUIVUS MAIOREM LICENTIAL NATURA CONCESSIT QUIS AUT DE GANYMEDI
RAPTU DUBITAT QUID POETAE VELINT AUT NON INTELLEGIT QUID APUD EURIPIDEM ET
LOQUATUR ET CUPIAT LAIUS. The comparative (MAIOREM LICENTIAL is noteworthy.
NATURE has granted ‘greater’, not exclusive license to affais with women than
to affairs with BOYS. The Latter are evidently NOT FORBIDDEN BY NATURE.
Discouraged perhaps, but not outlawed. This is a BEGRUDGING ADMISSION, in
perfect agreement with the tenor of the whole discussion of sexual passion
which had opened thus. ET UT TURPES SUNT QUI ECFERUNT SE LAETITIA TUM CUM
FRUUNTUR VENERIIS VOLUPTATIBUS SIC FLAGITIOSI QUI EAS INFLAMAMATO ANIMO
CONCPISCUNT TOTUS VERO ISTE QUI VOLGO APPELATUR AMOR – NEC HERCULE INVNEIO QUO
NOMINE ALIO POSSIT APPELARI TANTAE
LEVITATIS EST UT NIHIL VIDEAM QUOD PUTEM CONFERENDUM. (Cic. Tusc. 4. 68). These
words disparage sexual passion as a whole – particularly a hot, inflamed desire
(QUI EAST INFLAMMATO ANIMO CONCUSPICUNT) whether indulged in with women or with
boys. NATURA, according to Cicero, makes it easier to indulge in this passion
with women, so that when men DO INDULGE
IN IT WITH BOYS, they show just who DEEPLY THEY HAVE FALLEN VICTIM TO LOVE –
that treacherous and destructive power, ‘te originator of disgraveful behaviour
and inconstanty (FLAGITTI ET LEVITATIS AUCTOREM (4. 68), as G. Williams notes. In
fact, remarkably enough, Cicero later claims that love itself is not natural.
Cic. Tusc. 4 76. If love were natural, everyone would love, they would always
love, and would love the same thing: one person would not be deterred from
loving by a sense of shame, another by rational thought, another by his satiety
– ETENIM SI NAUTRALIS AMOR ESSET ET AMARENT OMNES ET SEMPER AMARENT ET IDEM
AMARENT NEQUE ALIUM PUDOR ALIUM COGITATIO ALIUM SATIETAS DETERRERET. Cicero’s
remark on NATURA and sexual relations with women is in fact fact little more
than a a passing comment. Still, its implications deserve some consideration.
In what whays does NATURE grant ‘greater permisiveness’ to a relation with aa
woma than with a boy? Why does Seneca suggest that men’s MALENESS ought to preclude
them from being PENETRATED, and why does Musonius Rufus condemn ALL SEXUAL
PRACTICES BETWEEN MALES as unnatural? These philosophers’ comments seem to rest
on certain assumptions about the function of sexual organs. Certainly Seneca
emphasixes the notion of the proper order or debitus ordon, according to which
men should not drink wine before eating, grow roses in the winter, build
buildings over the sea, or PENETRATE MALES. In short, some kind of ARGUMENT
FROM DESIGN seems to lruk in the backgrounf of Cicero’s Seneca’s and Musoniu’s
claism. The penis is ‘designed’ to PENETRATE a vagina. TA vagina is deigned to
be penetrated by a penis. Similarly the passage from Phaedrus Fables 4 16
discussed in chapter 5 implies, whitout actually using the word NATURA, that
males who desire to be penetrated (molles mares) and females who desire to
penetrate (tribades) have A FLAWED DESIGN. When Prometheus was assuming these
people’s bodies from CLAY, he attached the genial organs of the opposite sex in
a drunken slip-up. But his more popularizing account only specifies that those
males who DESIRE to be penetrated are anomalous. It does not designate those
men who seek to penetrate other males as unnatural. On this model, a sexual act
in which a master penetrated his UNWILLING MALE slave is NOT UNNATURAL. By contrast, according the
philosophers discussed here (Musonius most expliclty) this act would be
unnatural. But on the whole very few
Roman writers seem to have taken this kind of argument to heart. In general,
ROMAN MEN’S BEHAVIOURAL codes reflect an AWARENESS that the PENIS IS SUITED for
purposes OTHER than penetrating avagina, and that the vagina is NOT the only
organ suited for being penetrated. Such is the implication of a witty comment
in an epigram of Martial’s addressed to a man who, instead of doing the USUAL
WITHIN with his BOY and analyy penetrating him, has been STIMULATING THIS
GENITALS. This is objectionable because it will speed up the process of his
maturation and thus hasten THE ADVENT OF HIS BEARD (11.22.1-8). Martial tries
to talk some sense into his friend and the epigram ends with an APPEAL TO
NATURE. DIVISIT
NATURA MAREM PARS UNA PUELLIS UNA VIRIS GENITA EST UTERE PARTE TUA Mart 1
22.9-10. The comment is of course a witticigm. Note the logical
contradiction that this playful invocation of nature creates. If the penis is
designed by nature for girls and the anus for mmen,how can a man use a boy’s
anus in the way nature intended (i. e. to be penetrated by men) and at the same
time use his own penis in the way nature intended (i. e. by penetrating a girl?
See chapters 1 and 5 for further fsucssion of this epigram together with
Martial’s humorous invocation of the paradigm of nature with regard to
masturbation. but if the humour was to succeed, the notion that a boy’s anus is
designed by nature for a man to penetrate cannot have seemed outrageous to
Martial’s readership. After all, the rhetorical goal of the epigram is to steer
tha man onto the path of right behaviour, the path which Martial’s won persona,
dutifully, even proudly, followed. This sort of comment – rather than the
passing remarks of such philosophers as Cicero, Seneca and Musonius Rufus,
reflects the mainstreat Roman understanding of what constitutes NORMATIVE and
NATURAL sexual beavhiour for a boy and for a man. It is significant, moreover,
that neither CCicero nor Seneca nor Musonius Rufus nor any other survinving
Roman text, philosophical or not, argues that a MAN’s *DESIRE* to penetrate a
boy is ‘contrary to nature’. Musonius, for one, speaks ony of the sexual act
(SUMPLOKAI). We return to the Epicurean perspective offered by Lucretius cited
in chapter i. SIC IGITUR VENERIS QUI TELIS ACCIPIT ICTUS SIVE PUER MEMBRIS
MULIEBRIBUS HUNC IACULATUR SEU MULIEUR TOTO IACTANS E CORPORE AMOREM UNDE
FERITUR EO TENDIT GESTITQUE COIR ET IACERE UMOREM IN CORPUS DE CORPRE DUCTUM.
Lucr. 4. 1052-6. This are lines from a poem dedicated to teaching its Roman
readers about ‘the nature of things’ (de rerum natura 1.25). cf. Boswell p. 149
“Lucretius’s De rerum natura dealt with the whole of ‘natura’ but it was the
‘rerum’ of things – which suggested to Latin readers what modern speakers mean
by ‘nature’”. Obviously the SUSCEPTIBILITY OF MEN to THE ALLURE of boys and
women is a PART OF THE NATURAL ORDER for Lucretius. The beams of atomic
particles that EMANATE from the bodies of boys and women and attract men to
them are an integral part of the nature of things. It is the mentalitly evident
in such diverse textsa Lucretius’s poetic treatise On the nature of Things,
Martial’s epigrams, and graffiti scrawled on ancient walls that we need to keep
in mind when we evaluate the comments of Musonius Rufus, Seneca, and Cicero.
These are the words of three philosophers. Cicero expounding on the danger s of
love, Senceca inveighing against the corrputions of the world around him, and
Musonius arguing that men should engage only in certain kind of sexual
relations and only with their wives, the goal being the production of
legitimate offspring and not the pursuit of pleasure. These pronouncements tell
u something about the world in which these three philosophers who made them
lived, and about what men and women in that world were actually doing. Seneca
for example is hardly fulminating about imaginary fices) but they tells us even
more about Cicero, Seneca, and Musoiuns, and their own philosophical
allegiances We have every reason to believe that comments like their rpersented
a minoriy opinion. Indeed, the men AGAINST whom Musonius argues, who believed
that A MASTER has absolute power to do ANYTHING HE WANTS to his slave, is
precisel that man shoes VOICE dominated the public discourse on sexual
practice. Moreover, as Winkler (p. 21) trenchangly observers, Seneca’s
condemnation of such ‘unnatural’ behaviour as growing hothouse flowers or
throwing nightime parties, ‘though articulated as universal, is OBVIOUSLY
DIRECTED AT A VERY SMALL AND WEALTHY ELITE – THOSE WHO CAN AFFORD THE SORT OF
LUXURIES Seneca wants ‘ALL MANKIND’ to do without”, It is telling, too, that
Cicero himself never makes this kind of APPEAL TO NATURA in the SEXUAL
INVECTIVE sscattered throughout the speeches he delivered in the public arenas
of the courtroom, Senate, or popular assembly (see chapter 5), and that the argument
appears NOWEHERE ELSE IN the considerable corpus of Seneca’s moral treatises.
Likewise, it is worth noting that Musonius Rufus’s who makes the most extreme
case, not only wrote his treatise in GREEK rather than Latin, as if to
underscore its distance from he everyday beliefs and practices of Romans, but as
a philosopher omitted to stoicis in a way that Cicero and and Seneca are not. As
Haexter reminds us, Cicero proposes manydifferent rhetorical and philosophical
positions in his speeches, letters, and dialogues, and Seneca’s epistles to Lucilius
offer a tentative and experimental mixture of Stoicism and other philosophical
schools (many of his earlier letters end with quotations from Epicurus, for
example). In any case, Boswell, cp. 130 citing ancient sources claiming that
the very founder of stoicism, Zeno, engaged in sexual practices with males
(perhaps even exclusively) tnote that many ancient stoics actually seem to have
considered the question of sexual praticess between males to e ETHICALLY
NEUTRAL. Finally, It is worth noting that both Seneca and Cicero were thought
not to have practiced what they prached. In a discussion of how Seneca’s
behaviour often stood in contracition to his own teachings, the historian DIO
CASSIUS observes that although he married well, Seneca also “takes pleasure in
older lads, and teachers Nero do to the same thing, too”. Dio 61 10 4. Tas te
aselgeias has praton gamon te epiphanestaton egme kai meikarious exorois exaire
kai tauto kai ton Nerona poietin edidaxe. The historian goes on to insutate
that Seneca fellated his partners, speculating on the reason why refused to
kiss Nero. One might imagine, Dio notes, that this was because he was gisuted by Nero’s penchant for
oral sex. But that makes no sense given Seneca’s own relations with his
boyfriends (61 10 5 o gar toi monon an
tis hupopteuseien hoti ouk ethele toiouto stoma philein elegxketai ek ton
paidikon autou pseudos on). The younger
Pliny (Epist. 7.4) informs us that Cicero addresses a love poem to his faithful
slave and companion Tiro. Of course neither of these pieces of information
tells us anything about Cicero’s or Seneca’s actual experiences. Cicero’s poem
could have been a literary game and the stories a out Seneca that constituted
Dio’s source may well have been unfounded gossip (For Cicero and Tiro, see
McDermott and Richlin. P. 223, Canatarella p. 103 assumes that they actually
ENJOYED A sexual relationship)). On the other hand, is it not impossible that
Cicero actually DID experience DESIRE for Tiro and that Seneca DID enjoy the
company of MATURE MALE SEXUAL PARTNERS. And abovre all it is important to
recognize that later generations of Romans (the younger Pliny and Dio) were
willing to IMAGINE THOSE THINGS HAPPENING. Dio’s gossipy remarks and Pliny’s
comments on Cicero remind us of the cultural
context in which a philosopher’s allusion to NATURA must be placed. Paolo
Casini. Keywords: naturismo, naturalismo, natura, nazione, patto sociale, la
legge naturale, l’uomo, contra natura. “antica sapienza italica” razionalismo,
la metafora della lume, illuminismo, Bruno, il patto sociale -- Refs.:
Luigi Speranza, “Grice e Casini” – The Swimming-Pool Library.
No comments:
Post a Comment