Grice
e Canio: la filosofia romana sotto il principato di Caligola -- il portico a Roma
– filosofia italiana – Luigi Speranza (Roma). Filosofo italiano. Porch philosopher, martyred in the reign of CALIGULA
(si veda) and mentioned by BOEZIO in his Consolazione della filosofia. Member
of the Porch. One of those who opposed Caligola. When Caligola ordered C. to be
executed, C. is said to to have thanked him, and to have gone to meet his death
calmly and without apparent concern. He is admired for his exemplary demeanour
by Seneca and BOEZIO Giulio Canio. Canio.
Grice e Cantoni: il Kant fascista –
filosofia italiana – Luigi Speranza (Gropello
Cairoli). Filosofo italiano. “Kant”. Filosofia
fascista.
Grice e Cantoni: l’implicatura
conversazionale delle literae humaniores -- Romolo e Remo; ovvero, il mito e la
storia – scuola di Milano – filoofia milanese – filosofia lombarda -- filosofia
italiana – Luigi Speranza, pel Gruppo di Gioco di H. P. Grice, The
Swimming-Pool Library (Milano). Filosofo milanese. Filosofo
lombardo. Filosofo italiano. Milano, Lombardia. Grice: “You gotta love Cantoni;
I call him the Italian Hampshire! Cantoni
philosophises on ‘anthropology’ and he has not the least interest in past
philosophies, -- only contemporary! – Oddly, he reclaimed the good use of
‘primitive,’ meaning ‘originary,’ and he has philosophised on pleasure and
com-placent – also on ‘seduction,’ and eros. It is most interesting that he
reclaimed the concept of ‘umano,’ when dealing with anthropology, as he
considers the ‘disumano’, and the ‘crisi dell’uomo,’ and also the ‘desagio
dell’uomo’ – He has philosophised on the complex concept of the ‘tragic’ alla
Nietzsche – and he dared translate my métier and Fichte’s bestimmung as ‘la
missione dell’uomo’! – Like other Italian philosophers they joke at trouser
words and he has philosophised on ‘what Socrates actually said’! My favourite
is his treatise on Remo and Romolo in ‘mito e storia’. In opposizione alla
tradizione storicista, idealistica crociana si occupa di cultura e storia
usando contaminazioni sociologiche e antropologiche. Per queste aperture venne
considerato uno dei maggiori promotori dell'antropologia culturale in Italia.
Nel solco del maestro Banfi e uno dei maggiori esponenti della scuola di Milano. Oltre
ai numerosi volumi pubblicati fonda le riviste Studi filosofici e Il pensiero
critico. Fu allievo di Banfi, amico di Sereni e Formaggio. Nella cerchia
di amicizie di Banfi conobbe Antonia Pozzi che di lui si innamorò di amore non
corrisposto. In una lettera a Sereni ella scrisse. Non riesco nemmeno a trarre
un senso da tutti questi giorni che abbiamo vissuto insieme: sono qui, in
questa pausa di solitudine, come un po' d'acqua ferma per un attimo sopra un
masso sporgente in mezzo alla cascata, che aspetta di precipitare ancora. Vivo
come se un torrente mi attraversasse; tutto ha un senso di così immediata fine,
e è sogno che sa d'esser sogno, eppure mi strappa con così violente braccia via
dalla realtà. Sempre così smisuratamente perduta ai margini della vita
reale: difficilmente la vita reale mi avrà e se mi avrà sarà la fine di tutto
quello che c'è di meno banale in me. Forse davvero il mio destino sarà di
scrivere dei bei libri per i bambini che non avrò avuti. Povero Manzi: senza
saper niente, mi chiamava Tonia Kröger. E questi tuoi occhi che sono tutto un
mondo, con già scritta la tua data di morte. Un'ora sola in cui si guardi in
silenzio è tanto più vasta di tutte le possibili vite. C. define come primitivo
quel pensiero sincretico che non distingueva nettamente tra mito e realtà tra
affezione e razionalità. In questo senso "primitivo" assume una
valenza psicologica più che antropologica. Il pensiero mitico, scrive in
"Pensiero dei primitivi, preludio ad un'antropologia", non è
"arbitrario e caotico", ma pervaso di una razionalità, una razionalità
fusa in un crogiuolo affettivo. Yna delle differenze fondamentali tra il
pensiero moderno e quello primitivo consiste nel fatto che il pensiero moderno
ha una chiara coscienza della relazione e dell'intreccio delle varie forme
culturali tra loro e può sempre transitare da una all'altra quando lo voglia;
mentre noi sappiamo, ad esempio, che v'è un conflitto tra la scienza e la
religione, l'arte e la morale, il sogno e la realtà, il pensiero logico e la
creazione mitica, i primitivi mantengono tutte queste forme su di un piano
indistinto per cui fondono e confondono ciò che noi non sempre distinguiamo, ma
possiamo pur sempre distinguere. Questa mancanza di distinzioni nette è uno dei
caratteri più salienti della mentalità primitive. Quindi sogno e realtà
trapassano uno nell'altro e costituiscono nella loro saldatura un continuum
omogeneo. Si ocupa occupò con
prefazioni, traduzioni, curatele e altro di Kierkegaard, Dostoevskij,
Nietzsche, Kafka, Spinoza, Fichte, Renan, Hartmann, Huxley, Balzac, Jaspers,
Banfi, Durkheim, Sofocle e Musil. Altre saggi: “Il pensiero dei
primitivi, Milano: Garzanti); Estetica ed etica nel pensiero di Kierkegaard,
Milano: Denti); Crisi dell'uomo: il pensiero di Dostoevskij, Milano: Mondadori,
Milano: Il Saggiatore); La coscienza inquieta: Soren Kierkegaard, Milano:
Mondadori, Milano: Il Saggiatore; Mito e storia, Milano: Mondadori); La vita
quotidiana: ragguagli dell'epoca, Milano: Mondadori, (articoli apparsi su "Epoca"); n.
ed. Milano: Il Saggiatore); La coscienza mitica, Milano: Universitarie, (lezioni dell'anno accademico) Umano e
disumano, Milano: IEI); Il pensiero dei primitivi, Milano: La goliardica, Il
tragico come problema filosofico, Milano: La goliardica); La crisi dei valori e
la filosofia contemporanea: con appendice sullo storicismo, Milano, Goliardica;
Filosofia del mito, Milano: La goliardica); Il problema antropologico nella
filosofia contemporanea, Milano: La goliardica,
Tragico e senso comune, Cremona: Mangiarotti; Società e cultura, Milano:
Goliardica, Filosofie della storia e senso della vita, Milano: La goliardica,
Scienze umane e antropologia filosofica, Milano: La goliardica, Illusione e pregiudizio: l'uomo etnocentrico,
Milano: Saggiatore, Storicismo e scienze dell'uomo, Milano: La goliardica,
Personalità, anomia e sistema sociale, Milano: Goliardica); Che cosa ha
veramente detto Kafka, Roma: Ubaldini); Il significato del tragico, Milano: La
goliardica, Introduzione alle scienze umane, Milano: La goliardica); Che cosa
ha detto veramente Hartmann, Roma: Ubaldini,
Robert Musil e la crisi dell'uomo europeo, Milano: La goliardica, Milano:
Cuem); Persona, cultura e società nelle scienze umane, Milano: Cisalpino-Goliardica);
Antropologia quotidiana, Milano: Rizzoli); Il senso del tragico e il piacere,
prefazione di Abbagnano, Milano: Nuova, Kafka e il disagio dell'uomo
contemporaneo, con una nota di Montaleone, Milano: Unicopli). Attiva tra 1950 ed il 1962 e edita
dall'Istituto Editoriale Italiano
Lettere d'amore di Antonia Pozzi Carlo Montaleone, Cultura a Milano nel
dopoguerra. Filosofia e engagement in Remo Cantoni, Torino: Bollati Boringhieri,
Genna, «Il pensiero critico» di C., Firenze: Le Lettere, Massimiliano Cappuccio
e Alessandro Sardi, Remo Cantoni, Milano: Cuem, Reda, L'antropologia filosofica
di Remo Cantoni. Miti come arabeschi, Fondazione Ugo Spirito, Antonia Pozzi
Antonio Banfi Scuola di Milano Altri progetti Collabora a Wikiquote Citazionio
su Remo Cantoni Collabora a Wikimedia Commons Wikimedia Commons contiene
immagini o altri file su Remo Cantoni
sito di Antonia Pozzi, su antoniapozzi. Filosofia Letteratura Letteratura Università Università Filosofo Accademici italiani Professore
Milano MilanoStudenti dell'Università degli Studi di MilanoProfessori
dell'Università degli Studi di Cagliari Professori della SapienzaRomaProfessori
dell'Università degli Studi di PaviaProfessori dell'Università degli Studi di
Milano Fondatori di riviste italiane Direttori di periodici italiani. Haverfield. The
Study of Philosophy at Oxford
A LECTURE DELIVERED TO UNDERGRADUATES READING FOR
THE LITERAE HUMANIORES SCHOOL. Lectures are seldom published singly
unless they have been read on ceremonial occasions to a general
audience and to which their style and subject are suitable. My present lecture
is not of that kind, since it is addressed to mere pupils, or ‘under-graduates’
– those below the minimum qualification here at Oxford, the B. A. But I am
delivering it to undergraduates beginning the study of philosophy at
Oxford, since H. P. Grice thought it would be a good idea, especially for those
pupils coming from, of all places, Italy. The purpose of my lecture, then, is
to set out in the plainest words the main features of that study. It aims
at emphasising three points. First, the need well known to all, but
realised by few, of the chronology of philosophy (e. g. Locke – Hume –
Berkeley) -- and still more of
geography (Cambridge to the south-west of Oxford), as geography is now
understood, in any study of philosophy (where is Koenigsberg?). Second,
the character of the Oxford philosophy course as a study of rather short
periods – say, philosophical analysis between the two world wars, to echo the
title of J. O. Urmson’s essay -- based on a close reading of the
authorities: H. P. Grice, and his followers. Third, the relation between Italian
and Oxonian philosophy – none -- which
by their very differences supplement each other to an extent which
learners and even teachers do not always see what is not there to be seen.
At the end I will say a word or two – but not in Italian! -- about the
connection between this course and the training of future researchers.
Some of my colleagues, who kindly read the lecture in typescript, told me
that, if published, it would help “those Italian pupils” and interest
others elsewhere who have to do with the study of philosophy. I once
had a pupil who began his Oxford course by reading for Classical Honour
Moderations. Reasons which I have forgotten made him change his plans
after a term or so. He took up Pass Moderations instead and I had
to teach him for that examination! He was very confident that he could
surmount the Pass hedges with complete ease, but I had soon to tell him
that the work he had done for Honours would lead him straight to a
heavy fall. He could translate Berkeley alright, or most parts of them. But
he had just no idea whatever of getting up its content – what Berkeley
meant --, and when one asked him the usual question, 'He meant what? ',
he was beaten. The difference which my pupil found to exist between
Pass and Honour Moderations is almost exactly the difference which, even
after recent changes, still divides Honour Moderations from “Literae
Humaniores”. This difference is not so much, as the language of our
Oxford statutes might suggest, a contrast between the classics on the one
hand and Ordinary-Language Philosophy on the other. It is, rather, a
variety of the old difference between Aoyoy and e'pyoz/, between
the language which is the form, and the fact, which is the content. I am
told that, in reading for Honour Moderations, a man learns how to
translate Cicero – or “Cicerone,” as the Italians miscall him -- and to
imitate his style. I know, by my own experience, that he hardly ever
learns what Cicero MEANT. A pupil may scramble through any page of the ACCADEMICA
with whih he shall be confronted, and you’ll soon find out that he is utterly
unable reproduce the matter of what CICERONE meant for any purpose whatever,
and if you ask him in detail why Cicerone called the thing “Accademica”, the
chances are that he does not know – or worse, care. In reading for
Greats, a man goes almost to the *other* extreme. Whether he can
translate CICERONE into reasonable Oxonian becomes a trite point. What he
has to know and what, I think, in general he does know, is what
Cicero MEANS – not just in ACCADEMICA, but in the concept of the ‘probabile’.
He may not know it with all the refinements and shades of meaning that an
accurate scholar such as Grice shall detect, but he does get a sound
general idea of Cicero's meaning – if not his ‘implicature,’ as I say. His danger now is that he neglects the
form. He is bidden to compose ‘the essay’ on a philosophical topic every week
for FIVE years! These essays are only too often ayamV/zara e? rb
irapaxpfjpa, agonised efforts at the eleventh hour, and, even if they rise
superior to such human frailty and are result of exhaustive and deliberate
reading in the dark chambers of the Sheldonian, both teacher and taught
tend to set more value on the essay’s *content* than on its *form* -- or
deliverance: lots of ‘ums’ to be expected. Sixty or eighty years ago the “Literae
Humaniores” School was considered to give a special training in lucidity
of language and in logical arrangement of matter. That has gone into the
background. Of the three great intellectual excellences which this School
might develop, powerful thought and profound knowledge and clear style,
the third now counts as least, if you can believe me. It is not a good resul, but
it is a natural one in a course which is so closely connected with concepts
and facts. Facts are the first need of the student of philosophy: who
wrote the Critique of Pure Reason, and why? Why did he choose such an obscure
Teutonic idiom to express his vague idea? He must know 'who did what when,’ and
hopefully, ‘where.’ Indeed, if he knows the facts of philosophy in the
order which they occurred (Anassagora after Anassimandro), he can often
reconstruct and interpret the long history of philosophy for himself.
There is a vast deal more value in dates than the most early Victorian
schoolmistress ever suggested to her classes. Half the mistakes and
misunderstandings in our current notions of modern Oxonian philosophy arise
from some belief that events – i. e. the publication of books, etc. -- happened
at OTHER than their actual dates. Much, for example, has been written
about the causes of the decline and fall of the Roman Empire, but why did
Marcus Aurelius addressed his memories to HIS SELF? Among these causes the
depopulation of Italy and of the Roman Provinces has been quoted as one
of the most important reasons for the creation of Oxford. But, when one
comes to examine the facts, it appears that a great deal that is urged
under this head is a transference to the Empire of an agrarian evil
which belonged to the Republican period and which probably lasted
only for three or four generations. Those who hold this evil wholly responsible
for the fall of the Empire, start with a chronological blunder, and
naturally do not reach even a plausible solution of their problem, as
Nerone would! So again in smaller problems. The critics of the Roman
Emperor CLAUDIO, the ancient parallel (as is generally said) to James I
(who reined over Oxford) usually omit to notice what sorts of events
occurred in what parts of his reign. As it happens, dates show that he,
or maybe his ministers, began with an active and excellent
policy. They boldly faced foreign frontier questions which had been
neglected or mismanaged by their immediate predecessors. They took steps
to amalgamate the Empire by romanizing the provincials. They
carried out numerous and useful public works. Dates also show that,
after some six or seven years of good administration, they fell
intelligibly enough into evil ways. We might indeed apply to Claudius the
idea of a quinquennium of five years' wise rule which is usually
ascribed to Nero. And curiously enough, if we go to the bottom of the
facts about Nero, we find that the outset of his rule was marked by no
want of unwisdom and crime and that the notion of a happy first five
years is a modern misinterpretation of an ancient writer who meant
something quite different. Begin history therefore with the plain task of
knowing dates and facts. Write them out large if you will, and stick them
up over your bed and your bath. There is another simple-seeming
subject which students of history, and above all of ancient
history, must not neglect. I have mentioned the old question, ' who
did what when ? ' There is an equally important question, 'who did what
where?' It is no good studying history, and above all ancient history,
without studying geography, and geography of the right sort. The
subject is, of course, held in little honour even at some Universities.
Cambridge lately issued a small series of maps to illustrate an
elaborate work on mediaeval history. On the first, or it may be the
second, of these maps, London is shown to be 33 miles from York and 43 miles
from Paris, while the sea passage from Dover to Calais is about 4 miles
long. This is, no doubt, an exceptional view of the world. But our
ordinary attitude to geography is little more satisfactory. Very often, when we
admit the subject at all, we confine it to lists of place-names and of
political boundaries, which are mere abstractions and convey
nothing definite to the average student. Or else, under the title of
geography, we bring in the important, but quite distinct study, of the
topography of battle-fields, a study which is not really geographical,
which is specialist in character, and which is suited properly to
those who are particularly interested in the details of ancient tactics
and strategy. If we are to make any- thing of geography, we must get
beyond this. We must treat it as the science which tells us about
the influence (in the widest sense) of the surface of the earth on
the men who dwelt upon it. In the earlier ages of mankind this
influence was enormous. It was far greater than it is in the
present day : it was greater even than in the Middle Ages. In the
youth of the world, in the days which we are still apt to picture to
ourselves as the ages of innocence and unconstrained simplicity and
pastoral happiness, man- kind lived in fear. He knew he was weak, weak
alike in his conflict with nature and his conflict with the
violence of other men. Whenever he advanced a little in civilization, in
wealth, in comfort, he was beset by terror lest hostile outside forces
should break in and destroy him and his civilization together. If he
looked back over preceding ages, he found one long tale of
wreckage, of nations that went down whole to a disas- trous death, of
towns stormed at midnight and destroyed utterly before dawn, of
unquenchable plagues, of con- suming famines. These evils came from many
causes. But among the causes the character of the earth's sur- face
is by no means the least potent, though it may not seem the most obvious.
Man had not then learnt to tunnel through mountains and traverse the
worst and widest seas, and thus ride superior to the great barriers
which nature has set between human intercourse. Nor had he acquired that
coherence of political government and social system which can sometimes
defy moun- tains or seas and successfully battle with pestilence
and hunger. He was ruled by his geographical environment. The
form in which this environment affected him was very definite. It was the
broad features of the earth's surface which then especially influenced
mankind that is, the general distribution of hills and of plains, of
moun- tain heights and mountain passes, of river valleys and of
gorges breaking these valleys up, of harbours and rocky coasts, of trade
winds which brought or failed to bring rain. All the simple and general
physical conditions which affect comparatively large areas in a more or
less uniform way, were felt to the full by the Greek and Roman
world. Illustrations of their influence are strewn broadcast over the
shores of the Mediterranean. That sea itself provides perhaps as
good an example as any. To-day it is a sea that belongs to many nations
; one dominant power in it is not even a Mediterranean state. Under
the Roman Empire, it was the basis of one state whose capital lay in its
centre and whose provinces lay all around it like a ring-fence. The
cause is to be found in geography. The Mediterranean is not merely,
as its name implies, a sea in the middle of the land : it has more
notable features. Though it is the largest of all inland seas, it is also
the most uniform. Its climate is the same throughout its length and
breadth ; its coasts are equally habitable in almost every quarter ;
therefore, it easily attracts round it a more or less uniform population
and men move freely to and fro upon it. It is no mere epigram that
Algeria is the south coast of Europe. Moreover, as modern strategists
have noted, it is dominated, as no other sea is, by the lands which
surround it and by the peninsulas and islands which mark it. Therefore,
it was singularly fitted to form the basis of any Empire strong enough to
control so large an area. It aided the formation of the Roman
Empire. It determined parts of its constitution, notably its semi-federal
provincial system. It provided the unity needful for its trade and
language and intercourse. We can mark the influence of this sea even in
pre-Roman politics. Though it was then divided up between Greeks,
Persians, Carthaginians, none of them were able to hold a part of it
without at least aspiring to extend their sway over the whole. Only in
the present day, when political unions have become stronger and
more coherent, is it possible for geography to be put in the
background. Let me give two more illustrations. To-day Italy
is a south-eastern power: she looks to Tripoli and the Levant, she finds
her outlets and she passes on her traffic from Brindisi eastwards, and
her sons are scattered over the eastern Mediterranean. But geo-
graphically if I may repeat a saying which is trite but nevertheless
valuable ' Italy looks west and Greece looks east', and in the
Graeco-Roman world this fact counted. Thanks to it, the earlier Roman
Empire, the Empire of Augustus and Claudius and Trajan, was a west-
European realm, and its greatest achievements of conquest and of civilization
lay in the western lands which we still call Latin or Romance. That
French is spoken in France to-day is (if indirectly) a result of
geography. Once more, under the normal conditions of to-day food is
brought to our great towns from considerable distances along railways or
good roads. We are not much troubled by geographical obstacles; we
find human nature a much worse impediment, and a strike hinders far more
than any mountain or river. In the ancient world as indeed in parts of
the mediaeval world when food was carried along ill-made roads in /
ill-made carts, towns were impossible unless food-stuffs could be grown
close by, and landed estates could not be worked at a profit unless
markets lay within easy reach. Throughout, we see the Greeks and the
Romans face to face with an external nature which dominated them as
it does not dominate us. If they were not, like the prehistoric races,
living in ceaseless dread, they were slaves to rudimentary difficulties.
It is these natural circumstances of geography that we cannot omit
from our study of ancient history. Hang up your maps beside your tables
of dates ; draw maps of your own, and if you would remember them
properly, measure the distances upon them. I venture to
recommend this method of studying geography along with history for a
further reason. It is the best way of studying geography itself
which ordinary students can use. The pure geographer too often
wishes to teach the facts of the earth's surface as facts by themselves.
He wishes, for instance, that the student should know the whole
configuration of France, its mountains, rivers, geology, minerals,
before he proceeds to realize the effects of these various features
on the history of the world. That is all very well for the specialist.
But, as one who has taught geography in Oxford for a good many years, I
am convinced that applied geography is far more easily learnt by
the ordinary man than this more theoretical and abstract science. By
applied geography I mean the geography of a district studied in definite
relation to its history, with definite recognition of which geo-
graphical features mattered in one age, and which in another, and which
in none at all. This method involves that association of ideas, that
learning of things in con- nexion with other things, which is in truth
the most stimulating and helpful of all aids to knowledge. Here, as
elsewhere, the motto of the teacher should be o-vv re 8v epxo/jLvc, not
in the sense of the teacher marching along with the taught, but of two
kinds of knowledge helping one another. 4. From these
preliminaries of time and space I pass to the actual study of ancient
history in Oxford. The chief characteristic of that study is its limitation
to short and strictly defined periods. Among these periods several
alternative choices are intentionally left open to the student. In Greek
history he may read, as most men do, the Making of Greece and the Great
Age of the fifth century. Or he may combine the fifth century with
the story of Epaminondas and Demosthenes and that curiously modern
figure, Phocion, though, for some reason, he will here find few
companions in his studies. In Roman history he may study the death-agony
of the Republic and the beginnings of the Empire under the strange
Julio-Claudian dynasty. Or he may confine himself to the Empire and
follow its fortunes till the end of Trajan's wars. Or thirdly he may read
though few care to do so the tale of the conquest of Italy and of
Carthage, the days which formed the great age of the Republic and the
glory of the Senate. In any case he is confined to one definite epoch of
no excessive length. Secondly, he will read this epoch
carefully with many and certainly all the most important of
the original literary authorities, and these he will read in the
original tongues. The study of a period of history through the medium of
translations is one which finds no place, at least in theory, in our
Oxford ancient history. This is a point, perhaps, which deserves
some notice in passing. In the present condition of classical
studies there is a strong tendency for men not merely to study ancient
history but even to research, with a very slight knowledge of the
classical languages. In the local archaeology of our own country this
tendency has existed for centuries, and' it has been usual to work
at Roman Britain without any knowledge at all of Latin. Abroad, the
tendency has been growing of late years. I have had lately to write for a
foreign publi- cation a paper in Latin on some Roman inscriptions
and I have been a little surprised at the Ciceronian words which the
editor of the publication has pointed out to me as too likely to puzzle
present-day students of Latin epigraphy. Now, it is probable that an
educa- tional course which studied Greek and Roman history through
translations might have a distinct, though obviously a limited,
educational value. But it is idle to pretend to go beyond a somewhat
elementary course without knowing the ancient languages. This
Oxford course has been made the subject of many criticisms. We are told
that history is one and indivisible, and that fragments cut out of their
context not only lose their educational value but become
meaningless. We are told secondly that it is absurd to omit all the
momentous occurrences which lie outside our limited areas. We are told
also that by confining students to one or even two periods we prevent
them from acquiring a variety of distinct interests and discussing their
various periods together and widening their respective outlooks. Of the
first of these I shall say some- thing in a moment. The other two in my
judgement amount to very little. It is quite true that our system
omits a great deal. But there are after all only two ways of learning.
You can learn a little of many things or you can learn much of one thing.
Unless you are a genius or a reformer you cannot learn a great deal
about many things. All education is in a sense selective. Here, as
so often, much good may be done by the free lance. He prevents our
selections from being clogged by pedantry. In the end, however, there
must be selection. Lastly, the third criticism, that the use of
limited periods limits the total width of interest and discussion among
the body of students, does not I believe apply in the very least to our
own system with its alternative periods and its extraordinary range
of general knowledge. Moreover, I am clear that, if a
limitation of periods has its evils, it has also solid merits. It has
been generally the English tradition to prefer the plan of learning
much about one subject to that of learning a little about many, and the
warning Cave hominem unius libri used often to be quoted by Oxford
scholars of forty or fifty years ago. It is a good maxim. For it
does not simply warn us against the tortoise who hides in his shell ; it
points out that the dangerous enemy is he who knows one subject with
exceeding thoroughness, who controls one weapon with absolute mastery
and precision. The student who really works out one short period of
history, knows one part at least of the ways of human nature. It is
impossible to over-rate the practical value of such a bit of accurate
knowledge of how men move and think and act. Moreover, as
educationalists are constantly and rightly observing, the power of
thoroughly getting up a limited subject, the complete mastery of all the
relevant details, is a very valuable power in actual life. It may be
obtained in other ways than through a brief period of ancient
history; it could not be gained by a study of ancient history at
large. 5. Ancient History is singularly suited to this method
of the intensive culture of a small plot. If the period chosen be not
very long or very ill-chosen, it is here possible to combine the
following advantages. First, we can bring the student into touch with
periods of the highest importance, periods which are full of the
most diverse interests and which allow the most different minds to
expand on political or constitutional or economic or geographical or
military problems. Secondly, we let him come to close quarters with the
great mass of the original authorities, whether written or unwritten,
so that he can compare the account of any event or problem which is
given him by Grote, or Bury, or his own tutor, with the actual evidence
on which it ought to be based. Thirdly, he can work at historical
writings written in the great style and really worth reading as
literature. There is no part of mediaeval or modern history of which all
this can be said with complete truth. There we have to face multitudes of
charters, family papers, legal documents, broadsides, which are far
too vast a chaos for a student to overhaul in the course of his
University career, and to compare with the conclusions based on them.
There, too, our authori- ties are for the most part not even literature
by courtesy. When we ask for original authorities, we are given
not a Gibbon but a mass of matter which has no value save as the
husk, too often the tasteless husk, outside a grain of fact. In ancient
history, when all is said and done, when the longest list of ' books to
read ' has been made out that the most conscientious tutor can devise,
the total will not exceed the powers of a reasonable student. You
will find, indeed, when it comes to lists of ' books to read', that the
philosophical teachers, not the historical teachers, will go to the
greatest length. 6. I have only one criticism of my own to make :
our limited period does ignore the unity of history. We ought to do
something for a view of history as a whole. Let me quote a historian who
is not, I fear, as much admired in Oxford as he used to be, the late Mr.
E. A. Freeman. He was a writer of the old school, on the one hand
much too fond of battles, sensations, emotions, and even rhetoric, and on
the other hand much too dependent on written sources and too cold to the
charms of archaeology. Perhaps his true greatness lay in the
realism with which he taught some of the greater general historical ideas
even though he hammered them home with a wearying emphasis. One such
idea of his was the unity of history, on which I will quote one of
his utterances : We are learning that European history, from its
first glimmerings to our own day, is one unbroken drama, no part of
which can be rightly understood without reference to the other parts
which come before it and after it. We are learning that of this great
drama Rome is the centre, the point to which all roads lead and
from which all roads lead no less. The world of independent Greece stands
on one side of it ; the world of modern Europe stands on another. But the
history alike of the great centre itself and of its satellites on
either side, can never be fully grasped except from a point of view wide
enough to take in the whole group and to mark the relations of each of
its members to the centre and to one another. These are true
words ; how can they be reconciled with our limited periods ? It may
occur to some that we lecturers should prefix or add to our ordinary
courses some special hours on universal history. Time, however,
would hardly allow for more than eight or ten such lectures ; the
lectures themselves could hardly be other than in some sense popular, and
it is possible that they would be better read in a book than delivered as
a dictation lesson. There is another remedy in each man's hand who
cares at all for the historical side of his Schools' work. He can read
what he likes of other and later periods of history in such books as may
suit his own taste. Even on the lowest plane of motives such
reading would not be wasted. It may be less true than it was, that Greats
is concerned de rebus omnibus et quibusdam aliis. But it is still true
that there is very little knowledge which does not at some point or
other help in the understanding of Greats' work. It is a School in
which a man can ' improve his class ' by not reading directly for
it. Let me now pass to the two individual topics of Greek and Roman
History with which Oxford students are concerned. People are apt to think
that they are just the same. The educational system which has
dominated Western Europe for the last three centuries sets the Greek and
Latin, language, literature, and history, side by side, as subjects which
may be studied and taught by the same men and the same methods.
Even now it is supposed in some places of instruction, that a man
who is competent, perhaps extremely competent, to teach Greek History,
will be equally competent to teach any part of Roman History. But we are
begin- ning to learn that Greece and Italy are not the twins which
they seemed to our forefathers. We know that the Greek and Latin
languages stood in their origins far apart ; that Latin, for example,
comes nearer to Celtic than to Greek ; and we shall have to
recognize something of the sort in reference to Greek and Roman
History. But here fortune favours us in a remarkable and indeed quite
undeserved fashion. For these two subjects are in reality so dissimilar
that their very differences form a rare and splendid combination.
Each supplies what the other lacks. Together, they remedy many of
the evils which arise from the limitation of the periods studied. They
differ, firstly, in the character of the original authorities for the two
subjects and in the different historical methods which the student
is constantly required to use. They differ, secondly, in the actual
events which they record and in the kinds of lessons which they teach.
The one shows us character and the other genius. The one confronts
us with the city state, the other with the full range of problems of a
world empire. The one exhibits the different forms of political
development proper to the brief life of Greece, the other the principles
of constitu- tional growth which was gradually unrolled in the long
history of Rome. 8. First, as to the authorities. Alike in his
Greek and in his Roman history, the Oxford learner has to deal with
a large part of the original authorities for the periods which he is
studying; he has to study those periods with definite reference to the
evidence of the authorities, to appraise their general value and to
criticize in detail the meaning of their various assertions. But these
authorities are by no means uniform. On the contrary, those which he
meets in Greek History and those which he meets in Roman History
are startlingly unlike. The history of Greece, at least during the great
age of the fifth century, depends on two first-rate historians, whose
works have reached us intact, and who form the predominant and
often the only authorities for the series of events which they describe,
Herodotus and Thucydides. Everything else that we know of this age can be
hung by way of comment or criticism, foot-note or appendix, on
their narratives. The evidence of lesser writers, of geo- graphical
facts, of inscriptions or sculptures or pottery, may be and often is very
valuable, but it is always subsidiary. This is especially true of Greek
inscrip- tions, which I mention here partly because I shall have
presently to say something of the very different character of Roman
inscriptions. By far the largest and the most important sections of Greek
inscriptions are lengthy legal or financial or administrative documents,
such as in modern times would be engrossed on parchment or printed
on paper. They are, indeed, just like those documents which the student
of early English History finds selected and edited for him by Bishop
Stubbs. There are, no doubt, other Greek inscriptions, such as
tombstones. But the epitaphs of Hellas can rarely be dated ; they rarely
belong to the historical periods studied in Oxford, and they rarely say
enough about the careers or official positions of the dead, or of
their heirs and kinsfolk, to be used for historical inductions.
Like Stubbs* charters, therefore, Greek inscriptions are best suited to
provide the foot-notes and technical appendices to connected literary
narratives. It is a curious and a pleasant chance which has given us for
a unique period of history both admirable narratives and a copious
supply of supplementary inscriptions. Turn now to Roman History.
The Roman historian has a different and more difficult task than his
Greek colleague. In the long roll of centuries which form his
subject, the literary narrative and the subsidiary evidence are often
defective and seldom united. Not one single writer is at the same time a
great writer and contemporary and continuous. The Republic has been
described for us by authors who either, like Livy, wrote long after most
of the events which they describe, or who lived at the time, like Cicero,
but wrote no con- tinuous history, while it is painfully true that most
of the ancient writers on the Republic have little claim to be
called good historians. Nor is this all. These writers, good or bad,
Polybius or Livy or Appian, are very imperfectly preserved ; our stuff is
fragmentary. We have to deal with a mosaic that has been shaken in
pieces : we have to form our picture out of patchwork. Nor, lastly, is
there supplementary evidence to aid us. Archaeology throws singularly
little light upon the history of the Republic. Excavations, like those
of Adolf Schulten at Numantia, have shed some light, and there is
no doubt more to come when Spain has been better opened up : more also
may perhaps be gleaned some day from southern Gaul. But the Republic
was one of those states which mark the world, but not indi- vidual
sites, by their achievements. Such in Greece was Sparta : and, as
Thucydides saw long ago, the history of such States must always lack
archaeological evidence. The Roman Empire was in many ways a new
epoch. It is natural that the authorities on which our knowledge
rests should be in some respects unlike those of the Republic. Continuous
literary narratives are still few, and their value is not very great.
Like many important political organizations, the Roman Empire was only
half understood by the men who lived in and under it or perhaps, as
Kipling says of the English, those who understood did not care to speak.
Not even the greatest of the Imperial historians, Tacitus, appreciated
the state which he served and described. He gives his readers, for
home politics, a backstairs view of court intrigues, and, for foreign
affairs, a row of picturesque or emotional pictures of distant and
difficult campaigns described with a total absence of technical detail
and a surfeit of ethical or rhetorical colouring. All the real
history of the centuries of the Empire was ignored by almost every
one of those Romans or Romanized Greeks who essayed to describe it.
Moreover, this literary material, like that of the Republic, is broken by
all manner of gaps. We have painfully to reconstruct our narrative
out of detached sentences and chance frag- ments and waifs and strays
from works which have perished. On the other hand and here
the difference between Republic and Empire comes out clearest the
archaeo- logical evidence for the Empire is extensive and extra-
ordinary. No state has left behind it such abundant and instructive
remains as the Roman Empire. Inscriptions by hundreds of thousands, coins
of all dates and mints, ruins of fortresses, towns, country-houses,
farms, roads, supply the great gaps in the written record and
correct the great misunderstandings of those who wrote it. Most of
this evidence has been uncovered in the last two generations : the
Empire, misdescribed by its own Romans, has risen from the earth to
vindicate itself before us. The largest part of this new material is
supplied by the inscriptions. A few of these are documents, such as
form the bulk of the Greek inscriptions which I have mentioned already,
and of those few some five or six at least are perhaps of greater
importance than any other in- scription, Greek or Roman, that has yet
been found. But the great mass are not in themselves individually
striking. Their value depends not on any special merits of their
own, but on the extent to which they can be combined with some hundreds
of other similar inscriptions. If Roman History is the record of
extraordinary deeds done by ordinary men, it is also a record of
extraordinary facts proved by the most ordinary and commonplace
evidence. The details directly commemorated in the tombstones or the
dedications or similar inscriptions which come before us seldom matter
much. It is no great gain to learn that water was laid on to one
fort in one year and a granary rebuilt in another fort a dozen
years later. But if you tabulate some hundreds or thousands of these
inscriptions, they reveal secrets. Take, for instance, the birth-places of
the soldiers, which are generally mentioned on their tombstones. Each
by itself is a trifle. It is quite unimportant that a man came from
Provence to die in Chester or from Asia Minor to serve at York. But,
taken together, these birth-places tell us the whole relation of the imperial
army to the Roman Empire. We can see the state gradually drawing
its recruits from outer and yet outer rings of population. We can see the
provincials beginning to garrison their own provinces. We can see the
growth of that barbariza- tion which befell the Empire when it was
compelled, in its long struggle against its invaders, to enlist
barbarians against themselves. From similar evidence we can deduce
the size of each provincial army ; we can even catalogue the regiments
which composed it at various dates and the fortresses which it occupied,
and can trace the strengthening or the decay of the system of
frontier defence. It is true, indeed, that inscriptions of this
character are not very easy for students to deal with. For they have to
be taken in unmanageable masses, and they often involve remote problems
of dating and interpretation. But selections, such as those of Wil-
manns or Dessau, will help the learner through, and the short courses on
Roman Epigraphy which are now given in Oxford will start him on his
road. I do not know whether I shall seem an unbending conservative
or a hopeless optimist or a liberal who is trying to make the best of a
bad business. But the facts which I have just stated suggest to me that,
in respect of the training which they give x in historical method,
Greek and Roman History, as studied in Oxford, fit into each other and
supplement each other in a most happy manner. . Almost every form of
authority, the first-rate narrative, the second-rate abridgement,
the stray fragment, the long legal document, the brief in-
scription of whatever kind, all the varieties of uninscribed evidence,
come before him in turn. He has to consider and weigh these, and, whether
he proposes in after life to research in history or prefers the active
business of trade or politics, he will gain much by the criticism
which this task imposes on him. To survey many state- ments made by
fairly intelligent men, many accounts of complicated and obscure
incidents, is to train the judgement for practical life quite as much as
for a learned career. We talk somewhat professionally of
archaeological evidence. It is well to remember that, if that evidence
had happened to refer to the present, instead of the past, we should call
it economic and not archaeological : so much of it refers to just the
things which engage the reader of an ordinary social pamphlet. If
Greek and Roman History thus supplement each other in respect of
historical methods, they do so still more in respect of the historical
problems of political life and of human nature which they bring
before us. In one or the other of them we find most of our modern
difficulties somehow raised, and in many cases one aspect is raised in Greek
History, another in Roman. In the first place, there is the contrast
of character and genius, which is really the twofold con- trast of
individualism as opposed to common action and of intellect as opposed to
practical common sense. Greek History is a record of men who were
extra- ordinarily individual, extraordinarily clever, extraordi-
narily disunited. Our Oxford study of Greek History, divorced as it is by
chance or necessity from the study of Greek poetical literature and of
Greek art, lets us forget how amazingly clever the Greeks were and
the place which intellect and language and writing played in their
world. Roman History, on the other hand, is the record of men
who possessed little ability and little intellect, but great force of
character and great willingness to com- bine for the good of their
country to produce a result which was not the work of any one of them.
The history of the Roman Republic in its best period, in the great
age of the Punic wars, is in very truth ' a long roll of extraordinary
deeds done by ordinary men '. This aspect of it is, of course, less
prominent in the later Republic, the period of revolution, than in
the greater epoch which we here so seldom study. But it reappears
with the Empire. Though the historians of the Principate generally talk
of nothing but the Princeps, we can detect throughout a background
of hard-working, capable, probably rather stupid governors and
generals in the provinces. If any one wishes to study the conflict of genius
and character, that conflict which a hundred years ago the English waged
with Napoleon, and to realize the defects of being clever and the
advantages of being stupid defects and advantages which (I am bound to
say) are overrated by the average Englishman he will find this in his
Greek and Roman History. There are few lessons for guidance in
practical life and politics which are so valuable as an under-
standing of this simple-seeming subject. Again, in respect of
constitutional history, Greece and Rome supplement one another in a
useful way. The history of Greece, and especially of Athens, is too
short to include a long and orderly constitutional development. But it
does teach a good deal about the nature and value of those paper
constitutions which are in reality political rather than constitutional,
but which play their part more particularly in the acuter crises of
almost all ages. Rome, too, in the earlier part of the death-agony of the
Republic, in the generation which began with the Gracchi and ended with
-Sulla, saw several of these pseudo-constitutions. But the Athenian
examples teach us most, if only because they are the work of an
intellectual race, which believed firmly in the value of things which could
be written down on paper. Rome, on the other hand, shows that
slow growth, here a little and there a little, of constitutional life
on which true constitutional philosophy is based. Nowhere can we
find so near a parallel to our English constitu- tion as meets us in the
flexible order of the Roman Republic and Empire. Nor is this all. Of most
con- stitutions, as of our own, we know the maturer years, but not
the details of the birth and infancy. But the Roman Empire is, as it
were, born before our eyes. The cold unostentatious caution of Augustus
may, no doubt, have left his contemporaries a little doubtful
whether the old had really died and the new been born, and the scanty
records which have survived shed an uncertain light. Yet the fact is
plain, and the manner in which it happened. ii. And thirdly,
Greek history sets forth the successes and failures of small states and
of ' municipal republics ', while Rome exhibits the complex government of
an extensive Empire. For the present day the second matters most.
Perhaps the world will never see again a dominion of city-states. The
fate of the Polis was sealed when Plato wrote his Politeia and called
for philosopher-kings. It was more decisively settled when the
Romans discovered that men could be at once citizens of a nation and
citizens of a town. The failures of the mediaeval Republics of Italy and
Germany to maintain themselves against the stronger powers of
Emperors and Tyrants simply emphasized the result. The world will have to
supply otherwise that intellectual and artistic splendour which has been
the finest fruit of the city-states. But the administration of a
great Empire concerns many men to-day and in a very vital manner.
Our age has not altogether solved the pro- blems which Empires seem to
raise by their very size the gigantic assaults of plague and famine, the
stubborn resistance of ancient civilizations and nationalities to
new and foreign ideals, the weakness of far-flung frontiers ; it
can hardly find men enough who are fit to carry on the routine of
government in distant lands. The old world was no better off. Too often,
its Empires quickly perished ; too often, they survived only through
cruelty and massacre and outrage. Rome alone did not wholly fail.
It kept its frontiers unbroken for centuries. It spread its civilization
harmoniously over western and central Europe and northern Africa. It
passed on the classical culture to new races and to the modern
world. It embraced in its orderly rule the largest extent of land
which has ever enjoyed one peaceable and civilized and lasting
government. It was the greatest experiment in Free Trade and Home Rule
that the world has yet beheld. I have limited myself in the
preceding remarks to ordinary matters which come in the way of
ordinary students. I am well aware that we can add to the Oxford
ancient history course other and more delightful vistas down the by-ways
of folk-lore and religion, of anthropology and geology. We can trace in
Herodotus, quite as plainly as in the Oedipus Tyrannus, that sub-
stratum of savagery which underlies all ancient and most modern life, and
which lay closer to the Greek, despite his intellectual refinement, than
to the less humane but more disciplined Roman. We can plunge into
the labyrinths of 'Middle Minoan' and classify 'protos' from all the
coasts of the Aegean and the Levant. We can trace from geological ages the
growth of the continents and seas and climates which made up the
background of the older Europe. These things are full of interest, and
for some minds they are both a relaxa- tion and a stimulus. They are not,
I fear, so well suited to all of us. There is, indeed, enough in the
nearer fields of ancient history for any student to fill his time
with the more obvious subjects of politics and geography and
economics and archaeology. He may even, if he wishes, find in his
prescribed books an opportunity of beginning to prepare himself for
research. He cannot, indeed, as in the Modern History School, offer as
part of his degree examination a dissertation on a subject chosen by
him- self, and I am not quite clear that, if he did, his thesis
would be worth very much. But his study of original authorities may teach
him not only how to weigh the statements of men for practical purposes,
but also to note how history is built up out of such statements. He
can even carry his examination of original authorities far enough to
approach the region of independent work, and to go through some of the
processes which are connected with the august name of the Seminar.
But, let me add, this historical course which gives the man who
wishes it a glimpse of what research work means, is not, and cannot be, a
full preparation for it. For that a further training is indispensable,
whether it be in archaeology or in any other subject, and that
training cannot be included in the ordinary curriculum, since it is only
a tiny fraction of the whole body of students which intends to, and is
fit to, pass on to research. The ordinary course lays the foundation
of general knowledge, without which it is useless to attempt any
advanced study. The advanced work prepares a few competent men for
original and inde- pendent research, and the function of the
Seminar in Oxford would seem to be to train such men, if they will
stay here, after they have finished the ordinary course. I had once a
pupil, an American, who wished to work for a ' research degree ' by
offering a disserta- tion on a subject in Roman History. He asked to
be allowed to attend two courses of my lectures, one a general
sketch of the early Empire, the other a some- what more advanced
treatment of Roman inscriptions. After a while, he asked if- he might
drop the latter course ; he had, he said, already heard a good deal
of it in his own American University. When I replied that in that
case he had better drop the elementary course also, he told me that this
was mostly new to him. It appeared, on inquiry, that his teachers had
given him no training in general Roman History ; they had taken him
through a series of important inscriptions, had explained to him the
persons and things which happened to be mentioned therein, and had said
nothing of other persons and things which chanced not to be
mentioned. This is, of course, not a fair specimen of University
education in America. It is, unfortunately, a rather good example of the
mistakes often made by those who are too eager to encourage advanced
study. I am told that I ought to conclude such a lecture as
this by practical hints on the way in which men should 1 read their books
'. The one hint I care to give is to attend to the matter and not only to
the manner. There are many devices which will help in this. It is,
for instance, an aid to some students to read their ancient texts
twice, in two different languages, first in the originals and then in
some translation, in English or French or German, using these translations
not as ' cribs ' but as continuous and (in a sense) independent
narratives. But different men work by different methods, and it is not
always easy to give sound general advice. An individual teacher may aid
indi- vidual men by advice suited to them personally, and his
personality may inspire whole classes. But general advice, a panacea for
every learner, is a rather dan- gerous thing. It is not, indeed, always
much use to give it. I remember a friend of mine who once attended
such a lecture as this. When I asked him what prac- tical good he had got
out of it, he told me that the lecturer advised his hearers to buy
pencils with blue chalk at one end and red chalk at the other and to
mark their Herodotus in polychrome. He bought the pencil : the day
after his examinations were over, he found the pencil still uncut. Remo
Cantoni. Keywords: Romolo e Remo; ovvero, il mito e la storia, Carlo Cantoni,
filosofo, Remo Cantoni filosofo, mito e storia, implicatura mitica, la morte di
Remo, prejudices and predilections, umano, preludio a un’antropologia, umano,
umanismo, literae Humaniores – literæ
Humaniores – Lit. Hum. il primitivo. Il
mito di Remo. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice e Cantoni” – The Swimming-Pool
Library.
No comments:
Post a Comment